[lit-ideas] Re: Hartiana

  • From: "" <dmarc-noreply@xxxxxxxxxxxxx> (Redacted sender "Jlsperanza@xxxxxxx" for DMARC)
  • To: lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx
  • Date: Sat, 28 Mar 2015 04:19:21 -0400

Hart's distinction between "oblige" and "obligate" (that we don't find in  
Cicero, but for that matter, neither in John Austin, that Hart knew well, 
after  editing his posthumous works) is the key for understanding, in a 
conceptual  analytic way, the problems he was tackling. It inspired others into 
the same  path, e.g. 
 
Kenneth Himmar, in his "Law's Claim of Legitimate Authority", now  in in 
Jules L. Coleman (ed.), Hart's Postscript: Essays on the Postscript  to the 
Concept of Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
 
We see we change from keywords to keywords: the oblige/obligate distinction 
 becomes a way to understand larger issues like none other that the law's 
own  claim of legitimate authority. 
 
A favourite quote from mine comes from Francome v. Mirror Group  Newspapers 
Ltd. [1984] 2 All ER 408 at 412, which again deals with these larger  
issues that the oblige-obligate distinction merely points at:
 
"The right to disobey the law is not obtainable by the payment of a penalty 
 or a licence  fee."

Of course, the type of obligation, call it legal, we are discussing, and  
which for Hart is best expressed by "obligating" qua verb, rather  than 
"obliging", has to be crucially distinguished from this  other keyword: 
validity.

Hart is a positivist at heart, and holds  that a duty is legally valid if 
it is part of the legal system (i.e., if it is  certified as such by the 
tests for law in that system). 
 
On top of that, one fascinating aspect of Hart's conceptual-analytic  
approach is that legal obligation may be provided with a specific conceptual  
analysis without incurring in the wrong idea that there are different  'senses' 
to the expression 'obligation'. 

A legal obligation  may be thus analysed as a content-independent reason 
that is both categorical  and pre-emptive in force. 

As Hart writes: "The recognition of an  obligation to obey the law must as 
a minimum imply that there is at least some  area of conduct regulated by 
law in which we are not free to judge the moral  merits of particular laws and 
to make our obedience conditional on this  judgment."
 
All these clarifications are possible in a framework like Hart based  on 
conceptual analysis.

In a message dated 3/27/2015 11:37:22 A.M. Eastern Daylight Time,  
donalmcevoyuk@xxxxxxxxxxx quotes:

"Provided the victim  managed to  escape without giving his wallet, they 
would NOT utter "I was obliged to give my  wallet". They would restrict that 
to the actual case  where the victim DID  as he was 
obliged to do."

and comments:

"This "NOT" is a  matter of conventional usage and perhaps even 
"implicature" of a defeasible  sort: it is not a "NOT" of a logical sort, 
unless we try 
to turn the convention  into some kind of analytic stipulation i.e. it is 
not a logical error (in any  serious sense) to say "I was obliged to give my 
wallet. But found this was one  of those times when I did not do what I was 
obliged to do - as in my pocket, in  addition to my wallet, I had a gun ." 
(Only a kind of empty-headed and  tendentious philosopher would seek to 
outlaw such a sentence by  stipulation.)"

Empty-headed seems figurative, perhaps like  'obligation'. Allegedly wrong 
ideas still happen within brains (or  'heads' if you must). Recall Hart's 
adage: "I may be MISTAKEN, but I'm NOT  CONFUSED." "Tendency" may be a nice 
way to qualify what Hart's view as the  'linguistic turn', a minor revolution 
that happened to occur (and due to him, in  part!) in his own premises: 
Oxford!

By the way, Hart's use may well  happen NOT to be 'conventional' (a 
theory-laden expression in need of  analysis itself): it can be just 
'educated', as 
have been accepted, among  utterers of Hart's generations. Understanding 
Hart entails understanding his  usage of words rather than merely label them 
'conventional', which perhaps were  not. But I think we do agree that what he 
has in mind is a mere  conversational implicature, which is surely 
defeasible. (Grice was interested in  these type of 'implicatures' because they 
allowed to disengage a Fregean talk of  'sense' into the conceptual analysis 
one 
was engaged in). 

If what is at  stake is obedience by coercion and obedience by commitment 
to the realm of  morality and legality, it may well be worth turning 
something into an analytic  truth -- the stuff of analytic philosophy, after 
all, 
given by sufficient and  necessary conditions and yet expressible in a 
proposition that is 'ceteris  paribus' in nature, to allow for the undeniable 
defeasibility of ALL 'legal'  concepts and conceptions. 

As for McEvoy's 'cancellation' of the  implicature, there are of course, 
two types of implicature cancellation:  contextual, or the 'it goes without 
saying' cancellation, and the one McEvoy  provides: explicit "But found this 
was one of those times when I did not do what  I was obliged to do, as in my 
pocket, in addition to my wallet, I had a gun'.  Grice did not make much, in 
HIS analyses, much of this distinction in the  type of cancellation, but it 
may well be  more important  than he thought when we turn to Hart.

More importantly, Grice later  concocted 'disimplicature' -- to say less 
than you mean -- and it is this that  might well apply to the two specimens 
above (about 'oblige'/'obligated') as  we deal with the alleged 
counter-example of a 'usage' which happens to be  *another* usage, neither 
Hart's nor 
Grice's, and one which ascribes  factiveness to 'obligated':

McEvoy goes on:

"This kind of usage is  too weak a basis to establish that "obliged" is, 
always or necessarily,  "factive". But even if we were to deem that "obliged" 
is "factive", this does  not explicate wherein lies the distinction between 
it and "obligated": for in  many cases of usage to say "I was obligated to 
give my wallet" also carries a  "factive" implication that one complied."

Applying Grice's  disimplicature, the alleged counter-example may be 
interpreted as an instance of  an utterer the meaning less than than he says -- 
in 
sharp contrast to the  utterer who implicates, who, by definition, means 
MORE than he says. Grice used  to call the former just 'sloppy' uses of 
expressions, but thought  'disimplicature' sounded more refined, and right he 
was 
too!

McEvoy goes  on to use the word 'sense' -- which brought to mind Grice and 
his Modified  Occam's Razor: "Do not multiply senses beyond necessity". 
McEvoy: "And the  whole argument also fails to explicate the distinction 
between 
being "obligated"  in a legal and in a non-legal [e.g. moral] sense."

I'm not sure we need  polysemy here. "Obligation", as the Latin dictionary 
entry under 'obligo'  reads, is monosemous. It does have figurative 
extensions, but these depend on  one literal sense, since a figure of speech 
(such 
as metaphor) can always be  accounted as a conversational implicature. 
"Legality" does have a different  sense from "morality" (hey, they are 
different 
expressions!), but obligation  does not have two senses. (Grice's analysis 
would try to provide the grounds for  the alleged priority -- valuational 
priority, he calls it -- of the moral over  the legal, incidentally -- so even 
if we are dealing with two expressions with  different senses, they may still 
be deeper connections within them; more  importantly, Grice looked for a 
conceptual analysis of the 'moral', as in 'moral  obligation' in terms of 
higher-order desire: it is by appeal to higher-order  desires that an 
obligation 
'cashes out', to use Grice's expression, in, to use  the usual Oxonian 
keyword here, "interest". Hart's separability thesis allowed  him to rest 
content as he was without having to provide these types of  concpetual 
analyses). 

In any case, 'obligation' (even 'obliging' v.  'obligating') may sound 
grandiose, and the Oxonian way is best illustrated  by sticking with the 
conversational modals here -- Grice's  favourite being "must", Hampshire's 
favourite being"should", and R. M.  Hare's favourite being the still colloquial 
phrase, "ought to". To  ascribe multiple "senses" to these simple colloquial, 
conversastional,  expressions seems the wrong philosophical way to deal any 
alleged  counte-rexample that may just rely on the recognition that an 
implicature or a  disimplicature is at play. UNIGUITY plus IMPLICATURE seems to 
do 
the job while  sticking with parsimony of explanation, when it comes to 
Oxonian conceptual  analysis. (This uniguity, rather than ambiguity, or 
monosemy, rather than  polysemy, of 'must' is best expressed in Grice's third 
book, 
"Aspects of  Reason"). 

McEvoy concludes: "So we still have nothing that shows that  Hart provided 
an important advance on the (banal) thesis that legal obligations  differ 
from non-legal ones in that legal obligations are perforce imposed by law  
whereas non-legal ones are not perforce imposed by law. JLS' "argument" from  
usage is the kind of "analytic" approach that gives philosophy of this sort a 
 deserved bad name."

If Hart's thesis is regarded as 'banal', perhaps  that's because in the 
mind of many philosophers, legal philosophy, which relies  on a rule of 
recognition, such as "Whatever the Queen in Parliament enacts is  law."
has a side to it that distinguishes it from theoretical areas of  
philosophy like metaphysics and epistemology. Even moral philosophy looks for  
something beyond what we may call this 'banal' legality.  And I happen to  
think 
it's post-analytic philosophy that has an even worse name! (whereas  
"Milliscent" is a rather pretty name).
 
Hart brought jurisprudence to the realm of the conceptual analysis that J.  
L. Austin and his group had been applied to all sorts of philosophical 
problems.  Hart also has a deep feeling for the latitudinal unity of what he 
was 
doing: his  editorial work on both Bentham and John Austin has been 
exemplary, and his rich  legacy was felt profusely both not just within but 
without 
Oxford, or as he  said, 'wesward the tendency strikes its  way'!

Cheers,

Speranza

References

Austin, John -- Works, edited by H.L.A. Hart.
Bentham, J. Of Laws in  General. ed. H.L.A. Hart. London: Athlone Press.
Grice, Studies in the Way of  Words.
Grice, Aspects of Reason.
Hacker, P. M. S. Sanction Theories of  Duty, in A.W.B. Simpson, ed. Oxford 
Essays in Jurisprudence: 2nd Ser. Oxford:  Clarendon Press.
Hart, H.L.A. "Are There Any Natural Rights?" Philosophical  Review, 64.
–––  "Legal and Moral Obligation," in A.I. Melden, ed.,  Essays in Moral 
Philosophy. Seattle: University of Washington Press.
–––  Essays on Bentham. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
––– The Concept of Law, 2nd ed.  eds. P. Bulloch and J. Raz. Oxford: 
Clarendon Press.




------------------------------------------------------------------
To change your Lit-Ideas settings (subscribe/unsub, vacation on/off,
digest on/off), visit www.andreas.com/faq-lit-ideas.html

Other related posts: