[lit-ideas] Re: Hartiana

  • From: "" <dmarc-noreply@xxxxxxxxxxxxx> (Redacted sender "Jlsperanza@xxxxxxx" for DMARC)
  • To: lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx
  • Date: Tue, 17 Mar 2015 08:22:42 -0400

In a message dated 3/17/2015 4:04:17 A.M.  Eastern Daylight Time, 
omarkusto@xxxxxxxxx writes:
"Law is just" is not a  tautology, since laws can be unjust.  

It all depends on the analysis, conceptual analysis, that is. This is a  
field for LEGAL PHILOSOPHERS (or philosophers simpliciter, since 'philosophy,  
like virtue, is entire', and to characterise Hart as a legal philosopher  
IMPLICATES he's not a good legal philosopher).
 
Oddly, this applies to a field of 'conceptual analysis', the analysis of  
'legal reasoning'. While many see this as merely 'playing by the rules', a 
judge  can deem a rule not a rule, especially if it's morally odious.
 
Thus, a judge in a ‘wicked’ legal system where the law on some issue is so 
 morally odious that, all things considered, the judge should not decide 
the case  according to the law at all, but rather should refuse to apply the 
law 
 
This particular scenario is discussed by Hart 1958; Hart 1994, chapter  9, 
section 3. This possibility is also noted by Dworkin (1986, chapter 3,  101–
108) in discussing whether the Nazis had law.
 
O. K.:
 
>"Law is just" is not a tautology, since laws can be unjust. 
 
I would distinguish between:
 
i. Law is just. (the title of Hart's book is, "The concept of law", not the 
 concept of "the law", but if this is a parody on Ryle, "The concept of 
mind",  the implicature might be that "the concept of the mind" sounds clumsy).
 
ii. The law is just.
 
iii. This law is just.
 
My favourite is (iii), since it involves one of my favourite  
demonstratives, alla Kaplan.
 
The language of Kaplan’s logic is that of modal first-order predicate logic 
 with tense operators and other additions. The additions include a 
distinguished  predicate ‘Exists’, a distinguished binary predicate ‘Located’, 
a 
distinguished  constant ‘I’, a distinguished constant ‘Here’, and a 
function-term ‘dthat’. 
 
So we should add the Kaplanian:
 
iv. Dhat law is just.
 
-- or unjust for that matter.
 
My reference to the alleged tautology (or contradiction, for Hart)  
expressed in the terse Latin adage,
 
v. Lex iniusta non est lex.
 
was meant to hightlight Hart’s characterizations of so-called natural law  
which some see as notoriously inadequate, notaby by Norman Kretzmann.
 
The locus classicus is: 

Norman Kretzmann, 
 
"Lex Iniusta Non Est Lex": 
 
subtitled:

"Laws on Trial in Aquinas’ Court of Conscience."
 
-- 33 AM. J. JURIS. 99, 101 n.5.
 
-- but surely Aquinas's source is Augustine. 
 
Kretzmann, who wrote the entry on the history of semantics for Edwards's  
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, and thus, can be deemed a lover of conceptual  
analysis like Hart was, explains that, alas, Hart mischaracterizes both saints 
 Augustine and Aquinas -- only Hart would call saint neither.
 
The point is also treated by Finnis and by C. Orrego in his "H.L.A. Hart’s  
Understanding of Classical Natural Law Theory", which, being so critical of 
 Hart, one is surprised it got published in the "Oxford J. Leg. Stud."
 
Hart allegedly misunderstood classical "natural" law theory in such a way  
that it warranted the suspicion that
he did not have a first-hand  acquaintance with that theory.
 
Which seems naïf in view that Hart's only academic qualification was a BA  
(later MA Oxon Lit. Hum.) and you have to admit that the classics -- except  
perhaps Carneades, who received his share of odious criticism for it -- 
were all  "into" natural law.
 
Twining naturally tried to defend Hart, as he should: "Hart has never  
claimed to be primarily an historian of ideas". The implicature being that when 
 
you engage in conceptual analysis you cannot engage _at the same time_ (as  
Isaiah Berlin thought he did) in the history of ideas. As a result of 
Hart's and  Berlin's polemics, indeed, Oxford (metaphorically) felt that she 
needed a  special chair and the Chair of the History of Ideas was instituted. 
 
The primacy of Hart over Berlin can be seen in that the professorship in  
the history of ideas (while named after Berlin) is only a visiting one. 
 
Twining's comment on Hart NOT being a historian of ideas comes from his  
review of a book by Lloyd, where he expresses surprise "at the amount and  
difficulty of the philosophy which Lloyd expects his addressees to absorb,  
when your average legal philosopher, in his teaching role, never averagely  
dares to do more overt philosophy than expound Aristotle on justice, Hobbes and 
 Hume on the nastiness of life without law, and _parts_ of Aquinas on 
natural  law. 
 
Cheers,
 
Speranza
 
 
------------------------------------------------------------------
To change your Lit-Ideas settings (subscribe/unsub, vacation on/off,
digest on/off), visit www.andreas.com/faq-lit-ideas.html

Other related posts: