[lit-ideas] Re: Hartiana

  • From: Donal McEvoy <donalmcevoyuk@xxxxxxxxxxx>
  • To: "lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx" <lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx>
  • Date: Fri, 20 Mar 2015 11:52:27 +0000 (UTC)

>Now possibly 'arbitrary' has the wrong ring to it. When  McEvoy proposed 
two problems with, as I recall three multiple choice  'solutions', or possible 
solutions, the underlying assumptions seemed to be that  the choice of one 
of the three given solutions -- (a), (b), or (c) -- would NOT  be 
*arbitrary*.>
This is correct and it is correct for nearly all legal problems: there are 
better or worse solutions, though it may be a matter of dispute which are which.
Btw, on the second of the two problems (which involved a written decision 
inconsistent with a previous oral decision), the same watchwords of "public 
confidence" and "deterrence" are a useful guide to the solution adopted. 
Clearly this kind of inconsistency undermines "public confidence" and should be 
deterred: from that pov, one of the three solutions is (almost certainly) the 
best.
This kind of 'systems-thinking' [involving notions like "public confidence" and 
"deterrence"] is often not explicitly acknowledged in the courts' stated 
reasoning - though nor is it explicitly denied. But, I suggest, it is very much 
there as a kind of W3 "core aims and values" by which legal decisions are 
arrived at. On a W3-based Popperian theory of law, we must take seriously that 
legal decisions are not the product merely of their stated reasoning but of 
many other things, especially W3.3 "core aims and values" that will be 
reflected in decision-making but may not be explicitly acknowledged.
DonalLondon
 



     On Friday, 20 March 2015, 9:36, "dmarc-noreply@xxxxxxxxxxxxx" 
<dmarc-noreply@xxxxxxxxxxxxx> wrote:
   

 In a message dated 3/20/2015 4:35:02 A.M. Eastern Daylight Time,  
donalmcevoyuk@xxxxxxxxxxx writes:
As the Dekker example shows, the law  arrives at the point where two 
sections with the same essential wording are  nevertheless interpreted so that 
they have very different effects: this cannot  be the upshot of 'words on a 
page' or 'what words mean' but is the upshot of a  problem-solving approach.

For the record, the European Court of Justice  decided in  

Dekker v Stichting Vormingscentrum Voor Jone Volwassen  (VJV-Centrum)  Plus 
(ECR I-3941) 

that pregnancy discrimination  was sex [or gender] discrimination without 
any requirement for comparing this  unfavourable treatment to a man [or male].

-- which leads us back perhaps  to Hart on 'approximative equality' (as he 
compares it to inequality) -- and its  role as the source of 'legal and 
moral obligation' _sic_ in that order (In other  sections of "Concept of Law", 
Hart goes back to the more 'normal' ordering:  'moral and legal'.
 
Hart discussion of 'approximative equality' seems to be based on his  
favourite example of strength (even the strongest loses his strength when he  
sleeps, is one of his observations), and interestingly, makes use of the  
'nature' vs. 'artifice' distinction -- which I'm sorry to find Grice  HATED.
 
The nature-artifice distinction dates back to Graeco-Roman times, and Hart  
and Grice (Hart was Grice's senior) are interested in different aspects of 
it.  Grice is into 'signs', and if laws are made up of words, they are made 
up of  signs, one would think -- they are 'coercive' -- "Law as coercive 
orders"  is section II of chapter II ("Laws, commands, and orders") in Hart's 
book. But  Grice (in 1948, "Meaning") that Hart quotes in his 1952 review of 
Holloway (one  of the few philosophical publications -- rather than 
specifically LEGAL  philosophical -- he wrote before his appointment as chair 
of 
jurisprudence)  says he finds the nature vs. artifice distinction 'artificial'. 
 
--- GRICE INTERLUDE: 
------ Grice thinks that while Hobbes is right in the _spirit_ of what he  
writes when Hobbes speaks of signs being either 'natural' or 'artificial' 
(and  even 'conventional') when it comes to Grice's use of 'mean', he finds 
that he  does not want to state -- as Hobbes and Peirce do -- that words ARE 
signs -- and  cfr. Hart's title of his review: "Words and Signs" -- He opts 
for 'natural' vs.  'non-natural', seeing that one may mean in a non-natural 
way which is yet not  'conventional' (and thus 'artificial'). 
 
The use Hart makes of the nature/artifice distinction is different: he  
speaks of of it in terms of this 'approximative equality', which seems to 
appear  as the source of both legal and moral obligation when it comes to 
redress 
(if  that's the problem) an inequality which may be natural by an 
approximative which  is artificial and conventional. Since this is liable to 
get the 
WRONG  interpretation, I should quote Hart verbatim:
 
He is talking of a 'system' of 'reciprocal' (nice word!) 'rights and  
obligations'. "Its effect is to create among individuals a moral and, IN A 
SENSE  
[emphasis Speranza's] EQUALITY to offset [redress?] the inequalities [_sic_ 
 plural] of nature."
 
Hart's "of nature" may connect with his rather minimalist view of 'natural  
law' which was so maximalist in CICERO: "Surely we cannot think that Athens 
and  Rome have different laws" --. Cicero is defending natural law as 
being, by  necessity, one. And the mention of Athens is particularly apt when 
Grice will  later claim a direct descent of Oxonian dialectic from Athenian (if 
not Roman)  dialectic.
 
On the other hand, what were the Stichting Vormingscentrum Voor Jone  
Volwassen (VJV-Centrum Plus) thinking? It does sound pretty foreign -- and does 
 
make you agree with Geary (whose brother lives in Denmark) that it's 
sometimes  easy to get to the spirit of the law skipping the Dutch letter 
altogether! 
 
(cfr. if I read McEvoy aright, what a law SAYS and what uses it may be put  
to -- via implication: "before Dekker prompted a special provision for  
'pregnancy-related disadvantages', pregnant women would find their cases 
subject  to comparison to some notional male equivalent of a pregnant woman 
(perhaps a  man with an 'unknown-to-science' but equivalent medical condition), 
and  employers would defend themselves by saying that they would treat that 
notional  male just the same as they did the pregnant woman. None of this was 
probably  within the "intention" of any lawmaker"). 
 
McEvoy criticises the concept of 'intention' in the lovely Platonic word  
(lawmaker) -- cfr. Hart refers to Hoady's idiolectal use of 'lawgiver') -- 
but I  am reminded that while Hart being Hampshire's senior, they contributed 
on a  lovely essay in pure philosophy of action, "Decision, intention, and 
certainty"  -- the result of a joint seminar -- that will provoke Grice to 
have his  "Intention and UNcertainty" instead, and which in any case displays 
the  centrality of the concept in Hart's legal (even) philosophy (with 
caveats -- a  law is a coercive order even if its original utterer (with 
attending intentions)  is an ex-operant (to use Grice's sarcasm).
 
Cheers,
 
Speranza
 
------------------------------------------------------------------
To change your Lit-Ideas settings (subscribe/unsub, vacation on/off,
digest on/off), visit www.andreas.com/faq-lit-ideas.html


  

Other related posts: