[lit-ideas] Re: Hartiana

  • From: "" <dmarc-noreply@xxxxxxxxxxxxx> (Redacted sender "Jlsperanza@xxxxxxx" for DMARC)
  • To: lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx
  • Date: Fri, 20 Mar 2015 08:19:35 -0400

My last post today!
 
In a message dated 3/20/2015 7:42:50 A.M. Eastern Daylight Time,  
omarkusto@xxxxxxxxx writes:
Perhaps Grice would have wanted to be introduced  as "our man at 
everything." However, the notion that, if one is good at  philosophy, one is 
equally 
good at metaphysics, aesthetics, philosophy of  science, philosophy of law, 
and whatever comes to mind under the heading  'philosophy of such and such' 
strikes me as a phantasy, and a hybristic one.  Even Bertrand Russell, who 
certainly was very broadly educated - honestly  probably more so than Grice - 
acknowledged that he didn't know much about  aesthetics, and didn't publish 
on it. 
 
Again, the source of this is the very wise and Aristotelian adage,
 
"Philosophy, like virtue, is entire".
 
This has a VERY COMPLEX logical form. If we think of Achilles, for example, 
 and his alleged virtues. Surely Aristotle was obsessed with bravery, as he 
 should. But surely, too, if Achilles was virtues, it is virtue as a 
'unity' we  should be looking at.
 
Grice was a captain with the Royal Navy, and we all know about coordinates  
in longitude and latitude. When he left the Navy to return to philosophy  
(although once a captain, always a captain) he applied Long. and Lat. to  
philosophy. He claimed that we are still talking about what Thales spoke,  
because Philosophy has LATITUDINAL unity.
 
And Thales did not just say that all is water. Since there is LONGITUDINAL  
unity, Thales was a philosopher, therefore, he philosophised in an unitary* 
 way.
 
So, if there is LATITUDINAL unity in philosophy, it means that legal  
philosophy fits somewhere. This is perhaps well expressed by McEvoy, in a  
different context, when he writes in Re: Hartiana:
 
"In the hands of "legal philosophers", 'legal philosophy' is effectively a  
form of 'philosophy-lite', that takes law-related issues as its  
subject-matter."
 
where the keyword is "PHILOSOPHY-LITE" (as used by McEvoy and Jim Wilson,  
"New and Selected Philosophy-lite" -- but not necessarily me). 
 
Take again Hart and Grice on convention. Hart speaks seriously of at least  
two-people scenario. Grice goes further and speaks of the New Highway Code 
he  once invents while lying in his tub. 
 
The idea is merely to enhance conceptual analysis. 
 
For by referring to this Highway Code, Grice is into something else:
 
"X [may be current] only for utterer U"
 
i.e. a 'convention' may not NEED two (or more) individuals, as Hart's usual 
 scenarios are.
 
X is current iff it is only U's practice to utter X in  such-and-such 
circumstances. 
 
In this case, U WILL surely have a readiness to  utter X  in  such-and-such 
circumstances -- even 'meaning' something. 
 
This is related to a slightly different scenario "in which X is NOT current 
 at all, but the utterance of X in such-and-such circumstances is part of  
SOME SYSTEM OF COMMUNICATION which U [ALONE] has devised but which has  
never been put into operation (like the highway code which I invent one day  
while lying in my bath)."
 
Or a legal system designed by von Wright (Hart loved what he called  
"Scandinavian legal philosophy" and he was ready to use the proper 
nationalistic  
label). (Keyword: Scandinavian realism). 
 
In that case, U surely HAS a procedure for X in, granted the  _attenuated_ 
sense (i.e. way) that U has envisaged a  possible  system of practices which 
WOULD involve a READINESS to utter X  in such-and-such circumstances."
---- Studies in the Way of Words, WOW,  p. 128.  (Cfr. Robinson Crusoe's 
legal system -- before Friday enters the  scene). 
 
When Chomsky read this (in Searle's compilation, "The philosophy of  
language", Oxford readings in philosophy, ed. by Warnock) he said,  
"Behaviourist!" in a bad tone, but neither Grice nor Hart are behaviourist in  
the old 
Watson-type style of 'machine-without-the-ghost' type of behaviourism  (even if 
for Hart it seems an analytic truth that a rule needs to be associated  
with some relevant behaviour -- or other -- 'manifested' as Witters would  
prefer).
 
Where exactly LEGAL Philosophy fits in Philosophy's latitudinal history may 
 well incite a dispute between Grice and Hart, which is where the fun of  
philosophy rests. 
 
"Philosophy, like Virtue, is One."
 
Or, if you prefer, there is only one problem in philosophy, namely all of  
them. 
 
Cheers,
 
Speranza
 
* Not to be confused with Unitarianism -- but related to it! I'm not  
surprised that Grice's philosophical unitarianism (cfr. 'virtue unitarianism)  
may provoke as much controversy as 'theological' unitarianism did -- 
especially  in Ancient Rome. 
 
Appendix on unitarianism. 
 
Unitarians trace their history back to the Apostolic Age, i.e. the life of  
Jesus and the decades immediately after his death, and claim this doctrine 
was  widespread during the pre-Nicene period, that is, before the First 
Council of  Nicaea met in 325. Many believe their Christology (understanding of 
Jesus  Christ) most closely reflects that of the "original Christians." (For 
a  discussion of the New Testament evidence, see Nontrinitarianism.)
 
While it is evident that other Christologies existed in the late 1st and  
early 2nd centuries, at least some Jewish-Christian congregations tended to 
hold  the view that Jesus was a great man and prophet, even the Son of God, 
but not  God himself. (See Ebionites.)
 
One of the earliest controversies over the nature of Christ that involved  
the propagation of "unitarian" ideas broke out at Rome during the episcopate 
of  Victor I (189–199). This was the so-called "Monarchian controversy", 
which  originated in a revolt against the influential Logos theology of Justin 
Martyr  and the apologists, who had spoken of Jesus as a second god. Such 
language was  disturbing to some. Justin's language appeared to promote 
ditheism (two gods).  The view, however, was defended by Hippolytus of Rome, 
for 
whom it was essential  to say that the Father and the Logos are two distinct 
"persons" (prosopa).
 
Some critics of Justin's theology tried to preserve the unity of God by  
saying that there is no difference to be discerned between the ‘Son’ and the  
‘Father’ (unless ‘Son’ is a name for the physical body or humanity of 
Christ and  ‘Father’ a name for the divine Spirit within). This sort of 
thinking, known as  Modal Monarchianism or Sabellianism, would one day lead to 
a 
compromise doctrine  that the Father and the Son are consubstantial (of the 
same being).
 
Other critics preserved the unity of God by saying that Jesus was a man,  
but differentiated in being indwelt by the Spirit of God to an absolute and  
unique degree. They thus denied that Jesus was God or a god. They became 
known  as "adoptionists", because they suggested that Jesus was adopted by the 
Father  to be his Son. This view was associated with Theodotus of Byzantium 
(the  Shoemaker) and Artemon.
 
So even at this early stage we find evidence of proto-Arianism (Justin's  
view) and proto-Socinianism (the Adoptionist view), though they were, as yet, 
 not fully formed. Both of these theologies have similarities to latter day 
 Unitarianism.
 
The Monarchian controversy came to a head again in the mid-3rd century. In  
259 the help of Dionysius of Alexandria, was invoked in a dispute among the 
 churches in Libya between adherents of Justin's Logos-theology and some 
modalist  Monarchians. Dionysius vehemently attacked the modalist standpoint. 
He affirmed  that the Son and the Father were as different as a boat and a 
boatman and denied  that they were "of one substance" (homoousios). The 
Libyans appealed to  Dionysius of Rome, whose rebuke to his Alexandrian 
namesake 
stressed the unity  of God and condemned "those who divide the divine 
monarchy into three separate  hypostases and three deities".
 
Another crisis occurred over Paul of Samosata, who became bishop of Antioch 
 in Syria in 260. Paul's doctrine is akin to the primitive Jewish-Christian 
idea  of the person of Christ and to the Christology of Theodotus of 
Byzantium  (adoptionism). To many his doctrine seemed plain heresy, and a 
council 
of local  bishops was held to consider his case in 268. The bishops found it 
easier to  condemn Paul than to expel him, and he remained in full 
possession of the church  with his enthusiastic supporters. However, the 
bishops 
appealed to the Roman  emperor, who decided that the legal right to the church 
building should be  assigned "to those to whom the bishops of Italy and Rome 
should communicate in  writing". It was the first time that an 
ecclesiastical dispute had to be settled  by the secular power. So Paul was put 
out of 
his  church.

------------------------------------------------------------------
To change your Lit-Ideas settings (subscribe/unsub, vacation on/off,
digest on/off), visit www.andreas.com/faq-lit-ideas.html

Other related posts: