[lit-ideas] Re: The Causal Theory of Perception

  • From: Omar Kusturica <omarkusto@xxxxxxxxx>
  • To: "lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx" <lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx>
  • Date: Wed, 5 Feb 2014 15:07:12 -0800 (PST)

The term 'illusion' can use some illumination. 'Illusion' usually refers to 
experiences in which we perceive an actual object but perceive it inaccurately; 
for instance, we perceive a real ship on the horizon but it appears to us 
smaller than it is, or more distant than it is, or perhaps we are incorrect 
about its shape or color etc. 'Hallucination' refers to cases in which we 
actually perceive objects that are not there, and here it is possible to have a 
visual hallucination and still retain an awareness that the perceived 'object' 
is not real, and it is possible to believe that the perceived 'object' is real. 
(Both cases are known medically.) The latter stronger case might be 
characterized as a delusion, at least as a temporary delusion. Austin in Sense 
and Sensibilia makes the point about Ayer's loose usage of 'illusion' and 
'delusion', frequently making it sound as if they were interchangeable.

Well, just saying, I am not making any metaphysical points here, just trying to 
distinguish the terms.

O.K.



On Wednesday, February 5, 2014 7:46 PM, Donal McEvoy 
<donalmcevoyuk@xxxxxxxxxxx> wrote:
 
There is much more in the last post by JLS than is addressed here: for example, 
we could detour into examining the so-called 'Argument from Illusion'. 

I have tried to indicate that there is much that commonsense gets generally 
right in this area - for example, the commonsense view that there is an 
'internal world' (of experience) and an 'external world' (which is independent 
of experience and which has causal affects on the 'internal world'). No one 
with commonsense thinks that when they shut their eyes the "objects" that 
disappear from view in their 'internal world' of experience disappear from the 
'external world' (nor is it a misuse to speak of "objects" in this way in order 
to make this point: it does not follow of course that the "object" as 
experienced in the 'internal world' is
 the same thing, for all purposes, as the "object" in the external world). Nor 
is it commonsense to think there is only my 'internal world' and nothing 
'external' to which it pertains and which causally affects it. All of this 
important stuff commonsense gets right and there is no valid philosophical 
challenge to commonsense here.

What happens is that in developing our theory of knowledge in commonsense terms 
we start to get into a mess: we might think all knowledge is derived from 
experience in some way, but then reflect that we only therefore have knowledge 
of what we experience - and therefore only knowledge of an 'internal world', 
for experience belongs in our 'internal world' not in any 'external world'. 
Soon our commonsense empiricism (our theory of knowledge) is rendering 
problematic whether there is any 'external world' as per our commonsense 
realism. 

It is notable that the main arguments
 against commonsense realism are not based on anything like a convincing 
argument that there is no distinction between an 'internal' and 'external' 
world, but on arguments derived from making a mess in our theory of knowledge.

Popper's view is that this apparent clash between commonsense realism and a 
commonsense theory of knowledge is real and unresolvable: and the solution is 
to reject one or the other. In Popper's view, we should reject the commonsense 
theory of knowledge as mistaken while accepting commonsense realism as 
(largely) true (as far as it goes). This point is one of the major underlying 
themes of "The Self and Its Brain": and Popper wishes to show not only how the 
mind looks in the light of his epistemology but indicate how this epistemology 
dovetails with everything we know about the workings of the brain and other 
sense organs.

In this model, what is important is not 'causal role'
 per se - for the processes are elaborate and multi-causal: what really matters 
is that the processes work in the way of 'trial-and-error'. We can have much 
more insightful discussion based on examining the details of this kind of model 
than speaking in terms of mere 'causal role'.

Of course, we do not experience the vast 'trial-and-error' processes that are 
involved when we open our eyes and experience 'seeing an object': we neither 
experience the vast evolutionary 'trial-and-error' history that underpins the 
eye we inherit from our ancestors nor do we experience the complex, rapid 
'trial-and-error' processes involved when that inherited eye (and its brain) 
springs into action when we raise our eyelid. But our models, including 
scientific models, can throw much surprising light on all these processes - 
much more light than we get by thinking about what it feels like when we 
experience 'seeing an object', as our experience is far from
 'transparent' as to how it is formed. 

Our 'experience is not transparent as to 'causal roles' either, as these must 
be allocated in terms of detailed understanding of the relevant processes.

Dnl
Ldn






On Wednesday, 5 February 2014, 14:00, "Jlsperanza@xxxxxxx" <Jlsperanza@xxxxxxx> 
wrote:
 
Wittgenstein showed the drawing to a student:

"What do you see?"

"A rabbit".

"Well, it's a duck, you know."

Strictly, what is seen is a _drawing_ of a duck (or rabbit), rather than a  
duck (or rabbit) itself. This is expanded by 

http://books.google.com/books?id=r5s27wymdh0C&printsec=frontcover&dq=Wittgen
stein+theory+of+perception&hl=it&sa=X&ei=WUHyUrnkM6HXygGjIQ&ved=0CC4Q6AEwAA#
v=onepage&q=Wittgenstein%20theory%20of%20perception&f=false

C. Good, "Wittgenstein and the theory of perception", where Good expands on 
Grice's correct analysis of 'see':

"I saw Elvis on television".

This Good contrasts with:

"I imagined Elvis on television"

because a causal link can be postulated between Good's having seen Elvis  
Presley on television and Elvis Presley. Similarly, an editor of the Longman  
Dictionary, one argued against including as an entry for 'horse':

horse: 1. a mammal. 2. representation of a horse, as in
 a painting.

Still, it is not unfair to regard the Causal Theory of Perception as a  
version of Representationalism, but then, as Grice notes, 'represent' is a 
trick  of a word (his favoured uses of 'represent' are cases as when we say 
that 
a  cricket team 'represents' England in an international match). 

Good regrets that Grice does not spend enough time on sensory evidence and  
behavioural output as it relates to verbs like 'see', but Grice does. True, 
in  1961, these references are merely sketchy, but in "Method in 
philosophical  psychology" (1975) he has attained the status of a Functionalist 
(alla 
D. K.  Lewis) and he's more than ready to reformulate perceptual beliefs (as 
we may  call them) in terms of both sensory input and behavioural output. 
His dismissing  such an account in the earlier 1961 "Causal Theory" may thus 
be explained by his 
 resistance to allow the last word to be the proponent 
of an 'ideal' or 'more  scientific' language than the ordinary language that 
he finds himself  articulating. 

The nuances he discovers and makes explicit go well beyond the rough  
generalisations of the type he was familiar with (and which were especially  
popular at Cambridge, where he is reading "Causal Theory") to the effect that  
meaning is use, which (as we can argue) is not. He therefore spends quite 
some  time in proposing counterexamples to alleged ordinary-language specimens 
that  would seem to refute the Causal Theory of Perception as it relies on 
more or  less transparent (and 'immune' or 'incorrigible') sense-datum 
reports. 

McEvoy has been exploring Grice's (and others') references to 'material  
object' (that Grice symbolises as "M") having property "Phi" (or P) or  
'possessing
 property P', as Grice prefers, and their references in causal  
accounts of verbs of perceiving such as 'see' and actual accounts of the  
phenomena 
involved. McEvoy distinguishes, properly, between the 'internal world'  (I 
think his phrase is) of the perceiving subject and the alleged 'external  
world' (where "M" belongs). He prefers to rectify the causal theory of  
perception via an evolutionary account that rules out more fine-grained 
accounts  
of the causal process involved as redundant for survival (or not). 

In "The Causal Theory of Perception", Grice keeps mentioning the Sceptic,  
and it should be borne in mind that his account provides a reason for the  
sceptic's doubt. I'm less sure other versions of the causal theory do.

Grice mentions in passing, too, 

http://www.hist-analytic.com/GRICE.pdf

for which I provide further material in ps, the argument from illusion (i)  
and Moore's proof of an external world (ii). He rather concentrates on 
different  types of implication that attach (or fail to attach) to sense-datum 
reports like  "It looks to me as if there is a red tomato in the basket".

Cheers,

Speranza

---

(i) The argument from illusion is an argument for the existence of  
sense-data. It is posed as a criticism of direct realism. Naturally occurring  
illusions best illustrate the argument's points, a notable example concerning a 
 
stick: I have a stick, which appears to me to be straight, but when I hold 
it  underwater it seems to bend and distort. I know that the stick is 
straight and  that its apparent flexibility is a result of its being seen 
through 
the water, 
 yet I cannot change the mental image I have of the stick as 
being bent. Since  the stick is not in fact bent its appearance can be 
described 
as an illusion.  Rather than directly perceiving the stick, which would 
entail our seeing it as  it truly is, we must instead perceive it indirectly, 
by way of an image or  "sense-datum". This mental representation does not 
tell us anything about the  stick's true properties, which remain inaccessible 
to us. With this being the  case, however, how can we be said to be certain 
of the stick's initial  straightness? If all we perceive is sense-data then 
the stick's apparent initial  straightness is just as likely to be false as 
its half-submerged bent  appearance. Therefore, the argument runs, we can 
never gain any knowledge about  the stick, as we only ever perceive a 
sense-datum, and not the stick itself.  This
 argument was defended by A. J. Ayer. A 
critical argument would be as  follows: Because the stick provides a 
contrasting surface in the surrounding  water, the bent appearance of the stick 
is 
evidence of the previously  unaccounted for physical properties of the 
water. It would be a mistake to  categorize an optical effect resulting from a 
physical cause as sensory  fallibility because it results from an increase in 
information from another  previously unaccounted for object or physical 
property. Unless the water is not  taken into consideration, the example in 
fact 
reinforces the reliability of our  visual sense to gather information 
accurately. This criticism, which was most  strongly voiced by J.L. Austin, is 
that perceptual variation which can be  attributed to physical causes does not 
entail a representational disconnect  between sense and reference,
 owing to 
an unreasonable segregation of parts from  the perceived object. Further 
arguments are based on the extended mind theory,  which appeals to external 
sources of mental items. For example, the theory holds  that perception is the 
result of a complex interaction of mind, body and the  environment. This 
would rule out internal items such as sense data as referred  to in the 
statement of the argument.

(ii) Here is one hand is a philosophical argument created by George Edward  
Moore against philosophical skepticism and in support of common sense. The  
argument takes the form: Here is one hand, And here is another. There are 
at  least two external objects in the world. Therefore an external world 
exists. G.  E. Moore (1873—1958) wrote A Defence of Common Sense and Proof of 
an 
External  World. He posed skeptical hypotheses, such as "you may be 
dreaming" or "the  world is 5 minutes old", creating a situation where it is 
not 
possible to know  that anything in the world exists. These hypotheses take the 
following  form:
The skeptical argument: Where S is a subject, sp is a skeptical  
possibility, such as the brain in a vat hypothesis, and q is a knowledge claim  
about 
the world: If S doesn't know that not-sp, then S doesn't know that q; S  
doesn't know that not-sp; Therefore, S doesn't know that q. Moore's response: 
If  S doesn't know that not-sp, then S doesn't know that q; S knows that q;  
Therefore, S knows that not-sp. Moore does not attack the skeptical premise; 
instead, he reverses the argument from being in the form of modus ponens 
to  modus tollens. This logical maneuver is often called a G. E. Moore shift 
or a  Moorean shift. Moore famously put the point into dramatic relief with 
his
 1939  essay Proof of an External World, in which he gave a common sense 
argument  against skepticism by raising his right hand and saying "here is 
one hand," and  then raising his left and saying "and here is another". Here, 
Moore is taking  his knowledge claim (q) to be that he has two hands, and 
without rejecting the  skeptic's premise, proves that we can know the 
skeptical possibility (sp) to be  not true. Moore's argument is not simply a 
flippant response to the skeptic.  Moore gives in Proof of an External World, 
three requirements for a good proof.  (1) the premises must be different from 
the conclusion, (2) the premises must be  demonstrated, and (3) the conclusion 
must follow from the premises. He claims  that his proof of an external 
world meets those three criteria. In his 1925  essay A Defence of Common Sense 
he argued against idealism and
 skepticism toward  the external world on the 
grounds that they could not give reasons to accept  their metaphysical 
premises that were more plausible than the reasons we have to  accept the 
common 
sense claims about our knowledge of the world that skeptics  and idealists 
must deny. In other words, he is more willing to believe that he  has a hand 
than believe the premises of a strange argument in a university  classroom. 
"I do not think it is rational to be as certain of any one of these  ... 
propositions". Not surprisingly, those inclined to skeptical doubts often  
found Moore's method of argument not entirely convincing. Moore, however,  
defends his argument on the surprisingly simple grounds that skeptical 
arguments  
seem invariably to require an appeal to "philosophical intuitions" that we 
have  considerably less reason to accept than we have for the
 common sense 
claims that  they supposedly refute. The skeptical argument takes the form of 
modus ponens:  If A then B; A; Therefore B. Moore's argument flips the 
modus ponens structure  into a modus tollens: If A then B; Not B; Therefore not 
A. This illustrates Fred  Dretske's aphorism that "[o]ne man's modus ponens 
is another man's modus  tollens". Appeals of this type are subsequently 
often called "Moorean facts". "A  Moorean fact [is] one of those things that we 
know better than we know the  premises of any philosophical argument to the 
contrary" The "here is one hand"  idea, in addition to fueling Moore's own 
work, deeply influenced Ludwig  Wittgenstein, whose last writings were 
devoted to a new approach to Moore's  argument. These remarks were published 
posthumously as On Certainty. See also:  Samuel Johnson, to whom is attributed 
the act of
 hitting a rock with his foot as  a "refutation" of immaterialism. 
References: G. E. Moore," Internet Encyclopedia  of Philosophy; Keith DeRose, 
Responding to Skepticism; Dretske, F. (1995),  Naturalizing the Mind, 
Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press. Kelly, Thomas. "Moorean  Facts and Belief 
Revision, or Can the Skeptic Win?". Princeton University.  Forthcoming in John 
Hawthorne (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, vol.19:  Epistemology.

------------------------------------------------------------------
To change your Lit-Ideas settings (subscribe/unsub, vacation on/off,
digest on/off), visit www.andreas.com/faq-lit-ideas.html

Other related posts: