[lit-ideas] Re: The Causal Theory of Perception

  • From: Jlsperanza@xxxxxxx
  • To: lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx
  • Date: Wed, 5 Feb 2014 09:00:17 -0500 (EST)

Wittgenstein showed the drawing to a student:
 
"What do you see?"
 
"A rabbit".
 
"Well, it's a duck, you know."
 
Strictly, what is seen is a _drawing_ of a duck (or rabbit), rather than a  
duck (or rabbit) itself. This is expanded by 
 
http://books.google.com/books?id=r5s27wymdh0C&printsec=frontcover&dq=Wittgen
stein+theory+of+perception&hl=it&sa=X&ei=WUHyUrnkM6HXygGjIQ&ved=0CC4Q6AEwAA#
v=onepage&q=Wittgenstein%20theory%20of%20perception&f=false
 
C. Good, "Wittgenstein and the theory of perception", where Good expands on 
 Grice's correct analysis of 'see':
 
"I saw Elvis on television".

This Good contrasts with:
 
"I imagined Elvis on television"
 
because a causal link can be postulated between Good's having seen Elvis  
Presley on television and Elvis Presley. Similarly, an editor of the Longman  
Dictionary, one argued against including as an entry for 'horse':
 
horse: 1. a mammal. 2. representation of a horse, as in a painting.
 
Still, it is not unfair to regard the Causal Theory of Perception as a  
version of Representationalism, but then, as Grice notes, 'represent' is a 
trick  of a word (his favoured uses of 'represent' are cases as when we say 
that 
a  cricket team 'represents' England in an international match). 
 
Good regrets that Grice does not spend enough time on sensory evidence and  
behavioural output as it relates to verbs like 'see', but Grice does. True, 
in  1961, these references are merely sketchy, but in "Method in 
philosophical  psychology" (1975) he has attained the status of a Functionalist 
(alla 
D. K.  Lewis) and he's more than ready to reformulate perceptual beliefs (as 
we may  call them) in terms of both sensory input and behavioural output. 
His dismissing  such an account in the earlier 1961 "Causal Theory" may thus 
be explained by his  resistance to allow the last word to be the proponent 
of an 'ideal' or 'more  scientific' language than the ordinary language that 
he finds himself  articulating. 
 
The nuances he discovers and makes explicit go well beyond the rough  
generalisations of the type he was familiar with (and which were especially  
popular at Cambridge, where he is reading "Causal Theory") to the effect that  
meaning is use, which (as we can argue) is not. He therefore spends quite 
some  time in proposing counterexamples to alleged ordinary-language specimens 
that  would seem to refute the Causal Theory of Perception as it relies on 
more or  less transparent (and 'immune' or 'incorrigible') sense-datum 
reports. 
 
McEvoy has been exploring Grice's (and others') references to 'material  
object' (that Grice symbolises as "M") having property "Phi" (or P) or  
'possessing property P', as Grice prefers, and their references in causal  
accounts of verbs of perceiving such as 'see' and actual accounts of the  
phenomena 
involved. McEvoy distinguishes, properly, between the 'internal world'  (I 
think his phrase is) of the perceiving subject and the alleged 'external  
world' (where "M" belongs). He prefers to rectify the causal theory of  
perception via an evolutionary account that rules out more fine-grained 
accounts  
of the causal process involved as redundant for survival (or not). 
 
In "The Causal Theory of Perception", Grice keeps mentioning the Sceptic,  
and it should be borne in mind that his account provides a reason for the  
sceptic's doubt. I'm less sure other versions of the causal theory do.
 
Grice mentions in passing, too, 
 
http://www.hist-analytic.com/GRICE.pdf
 
for which I provide further material in ps, the argument from illusion (i)  
and Moore's proof of an external world (ii). He rather concentrates on 
different  types of implication that attach (or fail to attach) to sense-datum 
reports like  "It looks to me as if there is a red tomato in the basket".
 
Cheers,
 
Speranza
 
---
 
(i) The argument from illusion is an argument for the existence of  
sense-data. It is posed as a criticism of direct realism. Naturally occurring  
illusions best illustrate the argument's points, a notable example concerning a 
 
stick: I have a stick, which appears to me to be straight, but when I hold 
it  underwater it seems to bend and distort. I know that the stick is 
straight and  that its apparent flexibility is a result of its being seen 
through 
the water,  yet I cannot change the mental image I have of the stick as 
being bent. Since  the stick is not in fact bent its appearance can be 
described 
as an illusion.  Rather than directly perceiving the stick, which would 
entail our seeing it as  it truly is, we must instead perceive it indirectly, 
by way of an image or  "sense-datum". This mental representation does not 
tell us anything about the  stick's true properties, which remain inaccessible 
to us. With this being the  case, however, how can we be said to be certain 
of the stick's initial  straightness? If all we perceive is sense-data then 
the stick's apparent initial  straightness is just as likely to be false as 
its half-submerged bent  appearance. Therefore, the argument runs, we can 
never gain any knowledge about  the stick, as we only ever perceive a 
sense-datum, and not the stick itself.  This argument was defended by A. J. 
Ayer. A 
critical argument would be as  follows: Because the stick provides a 
contrasting surface in the surrounding  water, the bent appearance of the stick 
is 
evidence of the previously  unaccounted for physical properties of the 
water. It would be a mistake to  categorize an optical effect resulting from a 
physical cause as sensory  fallibility because it results from an increase in 
information from another  previously unaccounted for object or physical 
property. Unless the water is not  taken into consideration, the example in 
fact 
reinforces the reliability of our  visual sense to gather information 
accurately. This criticism, which was most  strongly voiced by J.L. Austin, is 
that perceptual variation which can be  attributed to physical causes does not 
entail a representational disconnect  between sense and reference, owing to 
an unreasonable segregation of parts from  the perceived object. Further 
arguments are based on the extended mind theory,  which appeals to external 
sources of mental items. For example, the theory holds  that perception is the 
result of a complex interaction of mind, body and the  environment. This 
would rule out internal items such as sense data as referred  to in the 
statement of the argument.
 
(ii) Here is one hand is a philosophical argument created by George Edward  
Moore against philosophical skepticism and in support of common sense. The  
argument takes the form: Here is one hand, And here is another. There are 
at  least two external objects in the world. Therefore an external world 
exists. G.  E. Moore (1873—1958) wrote A Defence of Common Sense and Proof of 
an 
External  World. He posed skeptical hypotheses, such as "you may be 
dreaming" or "the  world is 5 minutes old", creating a situation where it is 
not 
possible to know  that anything in the world exists. These hypotheses take the 
following  form:
The skeptical argument: Where S is a subject, sp is a skeptical  
possibility, such as the brain in a vat hypothesis, and q is a knowledge claim  
about 
the world: If S doesn't know that not-sp, then S doesn't know that q; S  
doesn't know that not-sp; Therefore, S doesn't know that q. Moore's response: 
If  S doesn't know that not-sp, then S doesn't know that q; S knows that q;  
Therefore, S knows that not-sp. Moore does not attack the skeptical premise; 
 instead, he reverses the argument from being in the form of modus ponens 
to  modus tollens. This logical maneuver is often called a G. E. Moore shift 
or a  Moorean shift. Moore famously put the point into dramatic relief with 
his 1939  essay Proof of an External World, in which he gave a common sense 
argument  against skepticism by raising his right hand and saying "here is 
one hand," and  then raising his left and saying "and here is another". Here, 
Moore is taking  his knowledge claim (q) to be that he has two hands, and 
without rejecting the  skeptic's premise, proves that we can know the 
skeptical possibility (sp) to be  not true. Moore's argument is not simply a 
flippant response to the skeptic.  Moore gives in Proof of an External World, 
three requirements for a good proof.  (1) the premises must be different from 
the conclusion, (2) the premises must be  demonstrated, and (3) the conclusion 
must follow from the premises. He claims  that his proof of an external 
world meets those three criteria. In his 1925  essay A Defence of Common Sense 
he argued against idealism and skepticism toward  the external world on the 
grounds that they could not give reasons to accept  their metaphysical 
premises that were more plausible than the reasons we have to  accept the 
common 
sense claims about our knowledge of the world that skeptics  and idealists 
must deny. In other words, he is more willing to believe that he  has a hand 
than believe the premises of a strange argument in a university  classroom. 
"I do not think it is rational to be as certain of any one of these  ... 
propositions". Not surprisingly, those inclined to skeptical doubts often  
found Moore's method of argument not entirely convincing. Moore, however,  
defends his argument on the surprisingly simple grounds that skeptical 
arguments  
seem invariably to require an appeal to "philosophical intuitions" that we 
have  considerably less reason to accept than we have for the common sense 
claims that  they supposedly refute. The skeptical argument takes the form of 
modus ponens:  If A then B; A; Therefore B. Moore's argument flips the 
modus ponens structure  into a modus tollens: If A then B; Not B; Therefore not 
A. This illustrates Fred  Dretske's aphorism that "[o]ne man's modus ponens 
is another man's modus  tollens". Appeals of this type are subsequently 
often called "Moorean facts". "A  Moorean fact [is] one of those things that we 
know better than we know the  premises of any philosophical argument to the 
contrary" The "here is one hand"  idea, in addition to fueling Moore's own 
work, deeply influenced Ludwig  Wittgenstein, whose last writings were 
devoted to a new approach to Moore's  argument. These remarks were published 
posthumously as On Certainty. See also:  Samuel Johnson, to whom is attributed 
the act of hitting a rock with his foot as  a "refutation" of immaterialism. 
References: G. E. Moore," Internet Encyclopedia  of Philosophy; Keith DeRose, 
Responding to Skepticism; Dretske, F. (1995),  Naturalizing the Mind, 
Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press. Kelly, Thomas. "Moorean  Facts and Belief 
Revision, or Can the Skeptic Win?". Princeton University.  Forthcoming in John 
Hawthorne (ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, vol.19:  Epistemology.

------------------------------------------------------------------
To change your Lit-Ideas settings (subscribe/unsub, vacation on/off,
digest on/off), visit www.andreas.com/faq-lit-ideas.html

Other related posts: