[lit-ideas] Re: The Philosophy of Law

  • From: "" <dmarc-noreply@xxxxxxxxxxxxx> (Redacted sender "Jlsperanza@xxxxxxx" for DMARC)
  • To: lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx
  • Date: Tue, 10 Mar 2015 12:49:42 -0400

How analytical can legal philosophy get: The  keyword is H. L.  A.  Hart.

Some say that analytical legal philosophy is, in spite of  its name, not 
MERELY an exercise in conceptual analysis. A pure conceptual  analysis playe a 
role in Hart’s legal philosophy. But some believe that this  sort of 
analysis is tangential to the main project of Hart's substantive theory.  His 
main 
objective in his opus magnum, "The  Concept of Law" is alleged to  be not 
essentially different from that of  Austin (not J. L. Austin)  namely,  to 
provide a reductionist theory of law. The main purpose of  Hart’s  theory was 
to offer an explanation of law in  terms of  something more  foundational in 
nature, that is, in terms of social facts,  which, in  turn, can be 
explained by reference to people’s actual conduct,  beliefs and attitudes. 
Hart’s objection to Austin’s reductionism was   not  to the idea of 
reduction but to the building blocks that  Austin  used in articulating his 
theory. Some think the main  METHODOLOGICAL   thrust Hart's legal positivism is 
reductionism, not thus analysis.  The  title of Hart’s opus magnum, "The 
Concept of  Law' (which should be "The  Concept of English Law", since this was 
the  only law he practiced) gave  the impression that some universal  concept 
of law stands for   something of  great importance, and that it  is somehow 
different from  an ordinary understanding of what the word  “law” means, 
yet awaiting  philosophical  elucidation. 

Of course the  word “law,” at has  many uses, such as in  “laws of nature,”
 “the  second law of  thermodynamics” and the like, that have  nothing, or 
almost nothing, to do  with law in its juridical use. Still  surely we 
shouldn't multiply the  senses of 'law' beyond necessity.  In fact,  law  is 
not 
 ambiguous, but uniguous. If we focus our attention on the  USES of   “law”
 in the juridical context,  some say is very doubtful that  there  is  
something that the concept of law 
stands for, distinct from   what people  ordinarily mean by the term -- 
which makes Hart a   botanist. Let us begin  with the obvious question, what is 
a   concept?  And what is it that we try  to do when we purport to  explain 
 or analyze the concept of X?
Gilbert  Ryle gave us a  pretty good sense  of what he meant by “concept”  
and what analysis  consists in. Concepts are not things,  as words are, but 
rather the  functionings of expressions, as keeping wicket is the  
functioning of the  wicket-keeper.  Very much as the functioning of the  
wicket-keeper  interlocks with the functioning of the bowler, the batsman and  
the   
rest, so the functioning of an expression, like 'law', interlocks with the  
functioning of  the  other members of the team  for which that  word is 
playing. One expression may have two  or more functions; but one of  its 
functions 
cannot change  places with  another. Clearly enough,  according to Ryle, 
concepts are  not abstract  objects. They are not  things of any kind.  A 
concept  designates  the myriad ways in  which a word is used by competent 
utterers of the relevant  language in a  given language – that is, ways  in 
which 
it plays specific roles in   making moves within  an interlocking set of 
other concepts and  arguments.  Some concepts  are more regimented than 
others, depending  on the particular discipline or setting in which they are 
used. 
But even  with   regimented or scientific concepts, Ryle thought, it would 
be  hopeless to  look  for a set of necessary and sufficient conditions  
that 
would  provide the set of  functionings a concept has in a  language. 
Rather we  are looking at piecemeal  examination of families  of conceptual 
connections, ways in which the functioning  of a word is  dependent on  
another. 
Furthermore, Ryle, like, in some ways, Grice,  believed that  these 
conceptual  connections are epistemically  transparent. 

A careful  examination  of the ways in which we  use language at particular 
settings is  obvious  to any competent user  of the relevant language. 
Because we know,  and  necessarily so, the  meaning of the words we use as 
competent members of  the  relevant  community, we will always be struck with 
the 
 undeniable  correctness  of any genuine conceptual connection whenever it  
is presented to  us.  How much and how far we can generalize from these  
connections, and how  deep  the solution they may 
provide for various  philosophical  questions, is not  entirely clear. Ryle 
clearly thought  that most  philosophical problems are  conceptual 
problems. Still, the  relation  between the meaning of an expression and the  
concept it  designates  is somewhat unclear. Expressions can mean different 
things,  depending on the  contexts or settings in which they are used. 
Ryle thought  that  one and  the same word can label different concepts. The  
concept  designated by  the expression “law” for example, would be  quite 
different when used in  a  juridical context from the same word  used, say,  
in the context of a theory  in  physics. Quite right,  but this does not 
answer our question.
Once  we identify the concept –  that is, the general  functionings of an 
expression in a  given type  of setting, say, “law” in the  juridical usage –
 is the concept   different from what the word means in  that general 
setting? To use the  familiar  Fregeian terminology: How  is concept different, 
if it is,  from sense? I am  not trying to suggest  that a concept is, after 
all,  some abstract object or  entity (as Frege  thought about sense). The  
question is more practical,  as it  were. When we try to elucidate or  
analyze a concept, is there  anything  else to it than figuring out  what the 
word, in its relevant settings,   means in the language in  question? 

It is difficult to see how it  would  be different.  Take the word “cricket”
 for example. We use the  expression  "cricket"  in English to designate a 
certain type of game. In short, the   word "cricket" in English has a fairly 
clear meaning or "sense",  designating a  certain type of game. Now we  can 
call this a concept,  if we like; we  can say that all reasonably  
competent users of  English have a concept of cricket.  But it is  difficult to 
see 
how  the concept of cricket is different from whatever "cricket" means 
in  its standard use in English expressions. If I asked you  to  tell me  
what cricket is, would you feel compelled to ask  me, “Do  you mean  the 
concept of cricket, or just the meaning of the expression "cricket", in  
English?
”  Giving me an answer to the first would also give me   an answer to the 
second.Now you might think that there is a   difference when other 
expressions are at stake such as "law". As we know, people  tend to have  
different 
conceptions of what "law"  is. And  thus it has become common to 
distinguish the  concept  from its  possible conceptions. We all understand 
the concept of law, it is assumed,  while we may disagree about its 
favoured conception.   

Now let us  focus on the concept. People have a concept of "law"   insofar 
as they  understand what the word "law" means, know what it   stands for 
and, by and large,  use it correctly in their  expressions.   And thus, by 
elucidating what the expression "law"  stands for, you have  given its meaning. 
At the same time, you have   explicated what the  concept is. Suppose, to 
illustrate, that someone  who  grew up in, say,  Mars, has absolutely no idea 
what "law"  is. (Cfr.  "The Senses  according to the Martians: a 
re-examination of  Grice's example" by   Coady). Let us assume that this 
Martian has  
never heard the word,  "law".  Now, having been found in Mars and  brought to 
Oxford, the Martian hears  the expression for the  first time (he is 
auditing a lecture by the Prfoessor  of Jurisprudence) and has the cheek to ask 
Hart what it  means. Let us  assume that Professor Hart (God bless him) gives  
the Martian a correct answer. Hart explain  everything that would   enable 
him to use the word correctly –  that is,  you give him the  correct meaning 
 of the expression in English. Is there  anything  left for him to know in 
order  to grasp the concept of  "law"?   Is there any point at which Hart 
can say  to the Martian, “You know   perfectly well what ‘law’ means, but you 
have not yet  quite grasped   the concept”? Some fail to see what this 
residual piece of   information  might be.

One might object to this by pointing out how the  mastery of   numerous 
expressions in a natural language requires not simply a    form of 
knowing-that,  but also some form of knowing-how; mastery of  a  concept is  
often a 
matter of habituation, like a skill we  acquire,  which takes time,  practice, 
etc. Those of   us who had to learn Classical Greek or Classical Latin know 
exactly how  frustrating  and difficult this process of  habituation often 
is. And  in fact  Hart suggests that there may be  pre-legal societies (or 
that  the  Anglo-Saxon society, back in the day, was  'pre-legal' -- "or had  
little respect for the predominantly Roman law that  applied in  England at 
the  time, when they (the Anglo-Saxons)  invaded"). But  this would not  
show that there is a gap between mastering  the  meaning of the expression 
"law" in a  natural language and  acquiring its concept. You do not really know 
 
what a word means  without an adequate grasp of  what it stands for and  
how to use  it in different contexts.  If it takes  habituation and  practice  
to acquire this kind of knowledge, that is what it  takes to  grasp  the 
meaning of the expression and be able to use it properly. 

Once you have acquired that competence, you have acquired the  concept, and 
vice versa. No residue is left here, in either    direction. Philosophers 
sometimes argue for conceptual claims that are  explicitly acknowledged as 
revisionist.
Such concepts are not meant to  reflect  an  agreement in judgments about 
the concept’s application to  all its  standard  cases. Therefore, 
counterexamples to the conceptual  claim,  based on  prevailing  linguistic 
intuitions 
or common  usage, would not  necessarily refute a  revisionist concept. It 
is  certainly possible to define a  concept that is revisionist  in  some 
way. But then the concept  would need to be supported by   theoretical 
arguments  about its  usefulness or theoretical purpose,  not by  anything 
traditionally called "conceptual analysis": an  analysis of  concepts is an 
analysis  of the ways in which an  expression functions in our actual  
languages, which  must be  based on observation of linguistic practices and  
prevailing   linguistic intuitions, such as Hart's. Conceptual analysis  cannot 
be   revisionist, unless it must. Is  there a point at which we can say,   “
Well, you may  have the concept of  law, but you do not quite know  what 
the expression "law" means”?  That some  find even more  mysterious.

If we assume  that  reasonably competent speakers of a  natural language 
know the  meaning of the word  "law" (in its  juridical "use"), they  
understand the concept of  law. And,  crucially, there is nothing  more to the 
concept than that which  is  
designated by the expression "law". This is what calls the “semantic sting”
  argument. Dworkin  claims that  Hart's conceptual analysis  of "law" is 
essentially,  about the meaning of the expression “law.”  One reply to  
Dworkin has been that Hart is seeking to  elucidate the concept of law, not the 
 
ordinary meaning of  the expression “law.”  People have pointed out that 
Hart   explicitly rejected the idea that  his theory is about the meaning of  
the expression  “law,” or that such an  attempt 
to define the  meaning of law would be  theoretically  fruitful (He had 
learned from  J. L. Austin and Grice and was more onto 'implicature'). If we 
are  right, however, that there is no   significant difference  between  
understanding the meaning of an  expression  (EXCLUDING  its implicatures, 
which 
are not part of the  expression's SENSE) and   understanding its concept, 
this line of  response is taking the wrong   tack. If you think (some  don't) 
that Hart’s theory of  law is  basically an attempt to elucidate  the 
concept of law, you would have  to agree with Dworkin that Hart’s  theory is an 
attempt to articulate  what the expression “law”  means. So it is a “semantic 
theory” after  all -- even cum metaphysics.  Grice's entitles the Part II 
to his WOW  (Way of 
Words),  "Explorations  in semantics and metaphysics". He  was trying to be 
provocative,  but  also holistic. 

Some think that Dworkin is right, up to a point. Dworkin is right to  
assume that conceptual analysis is, essentially, a linguistic inquiry --  what 
Austin calls 'botany'.  At least it has  been  so conceived  by the ordinary 
language analysis 
school of J. L. Austin,  to which  Hart  (half-"heartedly", if you allow me 
the pun, some think,  because  Austin looked  down on anyone his senior) 
belonged and which  he   was certainly influenced by. The idea  of a concept 
stands for  the  “
functionings of expressions in their settings,  and  ways in which these 
functionings  are intertwined with the   functionings of related concepts with 
which they  interact in a given   setting. Knowing what an expression 
means, and  consequently,  understanding  its concept, admit of degrees. In 
many 
cases  it  makes perfect sense  to say that A has a better understanding of 
the  meaning  of X than  B. Or that A’s understanding of the concept of X  
is more  complete than  that  of B. The idea that conceptual  analysis is  
transparent and   reveals something that can be  recognized upon reflection as 
obvious is only  made  plausible by the  assumption that it is our own 
linguistic  practices that we seek  to  elucidate here. Conceptual connections 
are  transparent because they  are  constituted by our language, and language 
 -- especially at  Oxford -- is public  and knowable to every competent  
user. Conceptual  analysis is,  essentially, about language.  We do  not mean 
to  suggest that  philosophical inquiry into the conceptual  connections  of 
language use is not  interesting or worth pursuing. The ways we use  
language  typically reveal a great deal  about the ways we think.  

Thought, however  – even if it is  collective and public, as  revealed by 
language use – is never a   guarantee of truth. The fact  that we 
collectively think about  something  in a certain way does not  mean that 
things are 
that way. Systematic  errors are not unheard of,  even if they are deeply  
entrenched in our language  use.
 
Dworkin’s  assumption is that that criterial semantics,  which he 
attributes  to Hart (not  unreasonably, given Grice's  influence), is incapable 
of 
explaining the  kind of “theoretical  disagreements” in law that he focuses 
on (Grice  said that conceptual  analysis is concerned with the analysis  of 
HIS  OWN concepts --  "That's what makes philosophy personal". He was also,  
 _contra_ Hart,  against specialisation in philosophy. Hart had become "Our 
 man in legal  philosophy". But Grice joked about this. "If I go to a  
university,  and  they introduce me to Mr. Poodle, our man in  
seventeenth-century  German  aesthetics", I infer the 'implicature'  (perhaps  
unintentional, 
but sometimes not) that Poodle is not even good at   seventeenth-century 
German 
aesthetics:  philosophy, like virtue,  is  entire."). (Grice uses scare 
quotes in 'implicature'  to simplify:  an  unwanted 'implicature' is not an 
implicature -- it's not like  an   unwanted baby, which is still a baby). 

The question is  whether Hart’s theory of law  is a form of  conceptual 
analysis at all  and, more generally, whether analytical   jurisprudence is 
best seen as  a form of conceptual analysis.  Austin’s  command theory of law 
seems  very intuitive, almost  compelling at first sight, and thus, by   
revealing its weakness  (usually on the basis of Hart’s critique), we  can  
motivate a  discussion of the hard questions about the nature of  law, opening  
the  way to more sophisticated philosophical accounts  presented to us  by 
philosophers  of the 20th century. Austin’s theory of  law  purported to 
provide a reduction of law to  facts of a social kind,   explicable in 
sociological terms. (And recall  that in Oxonian   circles, 'reductionist' was 
a term 
of abuse). 

Hart’s own  theory of law is as reductionist as Austin’s. Hart   clearly 
shared  Austin’s view that a theoretical explanation of the nature of  law   
should explain what the law is in terms of social facts, facts  that can  be 
 explained by more foundational truths about how people  behave,  the kind 
of  beliefs they have about their conduct, and the  kind of  attitudes and  
dispositions that tend to accompany those shared   beliefs. The hallmark of 
Hart’s theory is the idea  that social RULES of a  special type are at  the 
foundations of law, and  that social rules,  in turn, can be explained  
reductively in terms of  people’s actual  conduct, beliefs and attitudes. Hart’
s reductionist project has  been  blurred by his own  cryptic remarks on the 
importance of the internal  point  of view. 

According to   the common misunderstanding, Hart’s suggestion  that an 
adequate account of  the  normativity of law must explicate  the ways in which 
participants  in the practice  regard legal  requirements as reasons for 
their action,  is taken to indicate  that  Hart shared Kelsen’s 
anti-reductionist  critique of Austin. Hart  must  have meant, people assume, 
that  
there is something  misguided  about an  explanation of law’s normativity  in 
purely  sociological terms. 
But in  fact, it is the other way around.   Hart’s discussion of the 
internal  point of view is actually a  critique  of Kelsen, not so much of 
Austin. 
 

The point Hart makes about the internal point of view is that it can   be  
explained reductively (or behaviouristically), by observing   people’s 
actual practices, beliefs and attitudes. There is no   need, Hart claims, to  
postulate a presupposition of a basic 
norm,  as  Kelsen argued.

This is clear when Hart explains the difference between  the  rules of 
recognition  and Kelsen’s basic norm. 
 
Hart’s disagreement with Kelsen is  precisely about the   possibility of 
reduction. 

Hart strove to show  that there is no  need for such a  presupposition as 
Kelsen held about the basic norm. 

By  practice Hart means the actual  patterns of conduct  people exhibit, 
the  kind of beliefs they share about it and  the  attitudes that accompany   
those beliefs.

If, as some  claim,  the main methodological thrust of Hart’s theory of  
law, like  that of  Austin’s, consists in a reductionist project, where does 
that  leave  conceptual analysis? 
Is there a sense in which reduction of  some  type  of discourse or class 
of statements to another type or  class is a form  of  conceptual analysis? 
Recall Grice mocking Lewis  when Lewis said  of  conceptual analysts: 
"Clarity is not enough".  

A successful semantic reduction in any domain assumes that, if such a  
reduction is possible, it might constitute a form of  analysis that is,  
essentially, about language  (Waissmann was obsessed with this   when he spoke 
of 
'open-texture',  which may have 
influenced Hart's idea  of  defeasibility -- cfr.  "Excluders"). 

Then, there's the idea of a metaphysical reduction -- the  reductionism  
that  Grice found abusive -- is to show that a distinct  type of  phenomenon 
is actually constituted by, and fully reducible  to, some  other, more 
foundational type 
of  phenomenon. 

It is possible to construe Austin’s legal command theory as    attempting a 
semantic reduction as well. If this is the case, then   Hart  certainly did 
not share the objective. Nothing in Hart’s work   suggests that he  strove 
to provide a semantic 
reduction or that  he  thought such a project to be  feasible.

But Hart’s reductive theory  of law is  not JUST or 'merely' (to  use a 
word I borrow from McEvoy) an attempt   to explain how people  use the concept 
of law. It is an attempt to  explain  what law is in  terms of observable 
social 
behavior of human  beings. 


If you want to start  with a moral question about the legitimacy  of  state 
coercion or the legitimacy  of political authority or  whatever,  that is 
fine. It has been done for  centuries and is mostly  referred to  as 
POLITICAL, 
not LEGAL philosophy, of the  sort Hart  engaged in.  

Let us focus, as Hart doesn't, on essential   properties of  social 
practices. We   can say that it is an essential aspect of  cricket that it is a 
 
competitive  game  -- and Grice's favourite  game at that. Perhaps we need to 
qualify  this  statement. It is an  essential aspect of cricket, as we know 
it,  that it  is  a competitive game. For all we know, there might be  
Martians  who  “play” cricket not as a competitive game but as a  religious  
ritual; perhaps the  winning team becomes the high  priest.So it is  not really 
a game on Mars.  Whether Mars-cricket  is, in some sense,  cricket or not, 
is a difficult  question to answer,  but it is not  what is needed here. 
What is needed is  to realize that  the  characterization of cricket as a 
competitive game is not a   statement  about concepts or, generally, about 
language. It is a  claim  about  the nature of a certain type of human 
activity. 
And  whatever we  know  about cricket is not something we learn by mastering 
a language, but by   observation, learning and participation in this  
activity (preferably  at  Clifton). If you do not know, for example,  that 
cricket, as  played at  Clifton, where Grice learned it and learned  to play 
it, is  a competitive game,  that players must aim to win the  game, and 
that  what counts as winning is  
determined by the rules, you  will not  be able to play cricket, nor will 
you  understand what is going  on  when observing others playing it.  Some 
find  it boring. True   enough, you will also not know what the word “cricket”
  means, thus  
we  can say that you do not quite have the concept of cricket.   But  
learning that cricket is a competitive game is not something  that  comes about 
by learning to speak English; it comes about by  learning  about cricket, 
what it is and how to play it (or, at least, how  to  understand what  others 
are doing and aiming for when  playing  it).



Some allegedly essential features  of law have been identified by Hart  
(that  modern legal systems combine  primary and secondary   rules. And these 
features, and   others, are not mutually exclusive,  of course. The list of 
features  that  philosophers identify as  essential to law is not randomly  
selected. The  features serve some  theoretical purposes, highlighting  an 
aspect of law that  calls for  theoretical explanation and has some  
significance for the kind  of  theory offered. 
But there is nothing  question-begging  about  that.
 
There may be something ANSWER-begging, as Geary might prefer.

Legal interpretivism can critically engage  with what it  calls  the 
orthodox view if it denies the possibility of   reduction.

In his criticism of Hart’s jurisprudence, this is  precisely the  path that 
 Dworkin followed. Though not phrased  explicitly as an  anti-reductionist  
critique, Dworkin’s argument about  legal  principles aimed to show that 
Hart’s  rules of 
recognition cannot   provide a complete answer to what constitutes legal 
validity, because   legal validity is partly deduced by moral reasoning.  This 
is quite   clearly an argument that purports to show that legality  
cannot  be  reduced to social facts. Unfortunately, the interpretivist turn 
  in  Dworkin’s theory obscured this anti-reductionist argument, and led  
many  to  suspect, including Hart himself, that interpretivism and  legal  
positivism talk  past each other. Legal positivism, as Hart  clearly saw  it, 
aims to  provide the essential features of law quite  universally –  that 
is, wherever law  exists – whereas the impression  that Dworkin  left about 
interpretivism was that  it articulates a  theory of  adjudication for law. 
Some  think that Hart was not   quite right about this. There is a clear sense 
 in which Dworkin’s   interpretative theory challenges the reductionism 
inherent in  Hart’s   legal positivism. It aims to show that  legality cannot 
be reduced  to   facts about people’s conduct, beliefs and attitudes because  
legality   is partly, but necessarily, constituted by truths about  moral   
issues. Dworkin maintains that a  theory about the nature  of law must 
provide the  kind of explanation  that participants in the  practice can 
recognize, at 
least  upon reflection,  as something  that rationalizes for them the ways 
in which they   understand the  practice and its normative requirements. 

Let us examine the validity of Dworkin's criticism with an  example from  
Hart’s  account of social rules.

For a social rule to exist, Hart  maintains,  certain things must  be true. 
It must be the case that there  is some  regularity of  behavior manifest 
in the overt conduct of a  certain population,   and this conduct must be 
accompanied by certain  types of beliefs and  attitudes  that most individuals 
in that  population share about it.  For this  kind of reduction to be  
successful, it has to be shown that  the  explanation is  complete, and  that 
the elements offered are  sufficient to  distinguish social  rules  from 
other, similar  type of phenomena.Critics have argued,   however, that Hart’s  
explanation is not complete. In particular, it   cannot distinguish  between a 
case of following a social rule and one  of  complying with  a generally or 
widely accepted reason.
People often  exhibit a  regularity of behavior because they believe that  
there are  some  reasons that apply to the circumstances at hand, and thus 
they    comply with the reason and exhibit the same kind of attitudes that   
Hart  
associates with the “acceptance” of a rule. But,   nevertheless, it is not 
a rule they follow. 

These relates to strategies followed in  games, as when Grice's  obituary 
read that he was not an 'elegant' player, if 'effective' and 'strong'.  
Players of cricket are often  expected to know, as they do, that there  are  
certain things not done  in a game, for example, because it would  be a bad  
strategy. So, by  and large, they do not do them, and would  criticize others 
who do,  etc. However, such widely recognized strategies  do not form part of 
 the  rules of cricket. If you fail to comply, you  might be  criticized 
for  being foolish or amateurish (Grice preferred  "gentlemanly" -- but THE 
TIMES disagreed, and his obituary read: "Professional  philosopher and amateur 
cricketer") but not for violating a  rule of  cricket. What Hart may  have 
missed here (perhaps, we are not claiming  that  he did -- but he certainly 
was a worse cricket player than Grice) is  the  fact that following a rule 
requires the attribution of  a  reflexive type of  belief to those whose rule 
it is. 

The  difference between complying with a widely believed strategy  and   
complying with a rule consists in the fact that participants  regard  the  
existence of the rule as a reason for their action –  which is to  say that we  
cannot account for the relevant type of  belief people have  without 
invoking the  very concept that we try to  explain.

This would be a serious problem for Hart’s account if we  thought  that his 
theory about the nature of social rules was meant to  be a  conceptual 
definition. Then we would have to admit that he  was trying  to define what the 
concept  of a rule is in a way that  presupposes  that people understand the 
concept. But we do not quite see it  that way.  What Hart is trying to do 
is to provide an account of social  rules,   not a conceptual definition of 
what rules are. This account  purports to  identify the kind of beliefs and 
attitudes people must  have when following  a social rule.

It is not part of  Hart’s project to  provide a conceptual  analysis of “
rules,” or “social  rules” for that matter. His  project is to show what 
facts constitute the  existence of a  social  rule in a given population, and 
to show that we  do not need  to have more 
in our  toolbox for this purpose than the  elements  he identified, namely, 
regularities  of behaviour coupled with   certain types of beliefs and 
attitudes. 

A language like English  (which has words like 'law' and 'cricket', unlike 
Martian -- for all we know)  imposes certain constraints on  social 
explanations, but this is not the  main object. It certainly  does not mean 
that 
philosophical problems are  conceptual 
problems, or that  conceptual analysis forms the relevant  methodological  
foundations.  Every reductive explanation presupposes  that the class 
reduced to is,  in some relevant sense, more foundational  than the reduced 
class. 
But it  does not  have to assume that it is as  foundational as it  gets.

Cheers,

Speranza
 
Baker, G. P. Meaning and defeasibility, in the Hart festschrift.
Baker, G. P. Alternative mind styles, in PGRICE, Philosophical Grounds of  
rationality: intentions, categories, ends.
Grice, Studies in the Way of Words -- for a discussion of Hart on  
'carefully'. 
Grice, Intention and uncertainty. 
Hampshire and Hart, Decision, Intention, and Certainty, Mind. 
Hart, Words and signs: a review of Holloway, Language and Intelligence,  
Philosophical Quarterly
Hart, The concept of law.
 
------------------------------------------------------------------
To change your Lit-Ideas settings (subscribe/unsub, vacation on/off,
digest on/off), visit www.andreas.com/faq-lit-ideas.html

Other related posts: