[Wittrs] Chomsky, Universal Grammar and Culture -- Something New?

  • From: WittrFeed <wittrsfeed@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx>
  • To: language goes on holiday <wittrsfeed@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx>, "wittrs2feed@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx" <wittrs2feed@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx>
  • Date: Thu, 29 Mar 2012 10:44:34 -0700 (PDT)

Very interesting stuff here:

http://chronicle.com/article/Researchers-Findings-in-the/131260/

A Christian missionary sets out to convert a remote Amazonian tribe. He lives 
with them for years in primitive conditions, learns their extremely difficult 
language, risks his life battling malaria, giant anacondas, and sometimes the 
tribe itself. In a plot twist, instead of converting them he loses his faith, 
morphing from an evangelist trying to translate the Bible into an academic 
determined to understand the people he's come to respect and love.

Along the way, the former missionary discovers that the language these people 
speak doesn't follow one of the fundamental tenets of linguistics, a finding 
that would seem to turn the field on its head, undermine basic assumptions 
about how children learn to communicate, and dethrone the discipline's 
long-reigning king, who also happens to be among the most well-known and 
influential intellectuals of the 20th century.

It feels like a movie, and it may in fact turn into one—there's a script and 
producers on board. It's already a documentary that will air in May on the 
Smithsonian Channel. A play is in the works in London. And the man who lived 
the story, Daniel Everett, has written two books about it. His 2008 
memoir Don't Sleep, There Are Snakes, is filled with Joseph Conrad-esque drama. 
The new book, Language: The Cultural Tool, which is lighter on jungle 
anecdotes, instead takes square aim at Noam Chomsky, who has remained the 
pre-eminent figure in linguistics since the 1960s, thanks to the brilliance of 
his ideas and the force of his personality.

But before any Hollywood premiere, it's worth asking whether Everett actually 
has it right. Answering that question is not straightforward, in part because 
it hinges on a bit of grammar that no one except linguists ever thinks about. 
It's also made tricky by the fact that Everett is the foremost expert on this 
language, called Pirahã, and one of only a handful of outsiders who can speak 
it, making it tough for others to weigh in and leading his critics to wonder 
aloud if he has somehow rigged the results.

More than any of that, though, his claim is difficult to verify because 
linguistics is populated by a deeply factionalized group of scholars who can't 
agree on what they're arguing about and who tend to dismiss their opponents as 
morons or frauds or both. Such divisions exist, to varying degrees, in all 
disciplines, but linguists seem uncommonly hostile. The word "brutal" comes up 
again and again, as do "spiteful," "ridiculous," and "childish."

With that in mind, why should anyone care about the answer? Because it might 
hold the key to understanding what separates us from the rest of the animals.
Imagine a linguist from Mars lands on Earth to survey the planet's languages 
(presumably after obtaining the necessary interplanetary funding). The alien 
would reasonably conclude that the languages of the world are mostly similar 
with interesting but relatively minor variations.

As science-fiction premises go it's rather dull, but it roughly illustrates 
Chomsky's view of linguistics, known as Universal Grammar, which has dominated 
the field for a half-century. Chomsky is fond of this hypothetical and has used 
it repeatedly for decades, including in a 1971 discussion with Michel Foucault, 
during which he added that "this Martian would, if he were rational, conclude 
that the structure of the knowledge that is acquired in the case of language is 
basically internal to the human mind."

In his new book, Everett, now dean of arts and sciences at Bentley University, 
writes about hearing Chomsky bring up the Martian in a lecture he gave in the 
early 1990s. Everett noticed a group of graduate students in the back row 
laughing and exchanging money. After the talk, Everett asked them what was so 
funny, and they told him they had taken bets on precisely when Chomsky would 
once again cite the opinion of the linguist from Mars.

The somewhat unkind implication is that the distinguished scholar had become so 
predictable that his audiences had to search for ways to amuse themselves. 
Another Chomsky nugget is the way he responds when asked to give a definition 
of Universal Grammar. He will sometimes say that Universal Grammar is whatever 
made it possible for his granddaughter to learn to talk but left the world's 
supply of kittens and rocks speechless—a less-than-precise answer. Say "kittens 
and rocks" to a cluster of linguists and eyes are likely to roll.

Chomsky's detractors have said that Universal Grammar is whatever he needs it 
to be at that moment. By keeping it mysterious, they contend, he is able to 
dodge criticism and avoid those who are gunning for him. It's hard to murder a 
phantom.

Everett's book is an attempt to deliver, if not a fatal blow, then at least a 
solid right cross to Universal Grammar. He believes that the structure of 
language doesn't spring from the mind but is instead largely formed by culture, 
and he points to the Amazonian tribe he studied for 30 years as evidence. It's 
not that Everett thinks our brains don't play a role—they obviously do. But he 
argues that just because we are capable of language does not mean it is 
necessarily prewired. As he writes in his book: "The discovery that humans are 
better at building human houses than porpoises tells us nothing about whether 
the architecture of human houses is innate."

The language Everett has focused on, Pirahã, is spoken by just a few hundred 
members of a hunter-gatherer tribe in a remote part of Brazil. Everett got to 
know the Pirahã in the late 1970s as an American missionary. With his wife and 
kids, he lived among them for months at a time, learning their language from 
scratch. He would point to objects and ask their names. He would transcribe 
words that sounded identical to his ears but had completely different meanings. 
His progress was maddeningly slow, and he had to deal with the many challenges 
of jungle living. His story of taking his family, by boat, to get treatment for 
severe malaria is an epic in itself.

His initial goal was to translate the Bible. He got his Ph.D. in linguistics 
along the way and, in 1984, spent a year studying at the Massachusetts 
Institute of Technology in an office near Chomsky's. He was a true-blue 
Chomskyan then, so much so that his kids grew up thinking Chomsky was more 
saint than professor. "All they ever heard about was how great Chomsky was," he 
says. He was a linguist with a dual focus: studying the Pirahã language and 
trying to save the Pirahã from hell. The second part, he found, was tough 
because the Pirahã are rooted in the present. They don't discuss the future or 
the distant past. They don't have a belief in gods or an afterlife. And they 
have a strong cultural resistance to the influence of outsiders, dubbing all 
non-Pirahã "crooked heads." They responded to Everett's evangelism with 
indifference or ridicule.

As he puts it now, the Pirahã weren't lost, and therefore they had no interest 
in being saved. They are a happy people. Living in the present has been an 
excellent strategy, and their lack of faith in the divine has not hindered 
them. Everett came to convert them, but over many years found that his own 
belief in God had melted away.

So did his belief in Chomsky, albeit for different reasons. The Pirahã language 
is remarkable in many respects. Entire conversations can be whistled, making it 
easier to communicate in the jungle while hunting. Also, the Pirahã don't use 
numbers. They have words for amounts, like a lot or a little, but nothing for 
five or one hundred. Most significantly, for Everett's argument, he says their 
language lacks what linguists call "recursion"—that is, the Pirahã don't embed 
phrases in other phrases. They instead speak only in short, simple sentences.

In a recursive language, additional phrases and clauses can be inserted in a 
sentence, complicating the meaning, in theory indefinitely. For most of us, the 
lack of recursion in a little-known Brazilian language may not seem terribly 
interesting. But when Everett published a paper with that finding in 2005, the 
news created a stir. There were magazine articles and TV appearances. Fellow 
linguists weighed in, if only in some cases to scoff. Everett had put himself 
and the Pirahã on the map.
His paper might have received a shrug if Chomsky had not recently co-written a 
paper, published in 2002, that said (or seemed to say) that recursion was the 
single most important feature of human language. "In particular, animal 
communication systems lack the rich expressive and open-ended power of human 
language (based on humans' capacity for recursion)," the authors wrote. 
Elsewhere in the paper, the authors wrote that the faculty of human language 
"at minimum" contains recursion. They also deemed it the "only uniquely human 
component of the faculty of language."

In other words, Chomsky had finally issued what seemed like a concrete, 
definitive statement about what made human language unique, exposing a possible 
vulnerability. Before Everett's paper was published, there had already been 
back and forth between Chomsky and the authors of a response to the 2002 paper, 
Ray Jackendoff and Steven Pinker. In the wake of that public disagreement, 
Everett's paper had extra punch.

It's been said that if you want to make a name for yourself in modern 
linguistics, you have to either align yourself with Chomsky or seek to destroy 
him. Either you are desirous of his approval or his downfall. With his 2005 
paper, Everett opted for the latter course.

Because the pace of academic debate is just this side of glacial, it wasn't 
until June 2009 that the next major chapter in the saga was written. Three 
scholars who are generally allies of Chomsky published a lengthy paper in the 
journal Language dissecting Everett's claims one by one. What he considered 
unique features of Pirahã weren't unique. What he considered "gaps" in the 
language weren't gaps. They argued this in part by comparing Everett's recent 
paper to work he published in the 1980s, calling it, slightly snidely, his 
earlier "rich material." Everett wasn't arguing with Chomsky, they claimed; he 
was arguing with himself. Young Everett thought Pirahã had recursion. Old 
Everett did not.

Everett's defense was, in so many words, to agree. Yes, his earlier work was 
contradictory, but that's because he was still under Chomsky's sway when he 
wrote it. It's natural, he argued, even when doing basic field work, cataloging 
the words of a language and the stories of a people, to be biased by your 
theoretical assumptions. Everett was a Chomskyan through and through, so much 
so that he had written the MSN Encarta encyclopedia entry on him. But now, 
after more years with the Pirahã, the scales had fallen from his eyes, and he 
saw the language on its own terms rather than those he was trying to impose on 
it.
David Pesetsky, a linguistics professor at MIT and one of the authors of the 
critical Languagepaper, thinks Everett was trying to gin up a "Star Wars-level 
battle between himself and the forces of Universal Grammar," presumably with 
Everett as Luke Skywalker and Chomsky as Darth Vader.

Contradicting Everett meant getting into the weeds of the Pirahã language, a 
language that Everett knew intimately and his critics did not. "Most people 
took the attitude that this wasn't worth taking on," Pesetsky says. "There's a 
junior-high-school corridor, two kids are having a fight, and everyone else 
stands back." Everett wrote a lengthy reply that Pesetsky and his co-authors 
found unsatisfying and evasive. "The response could have been 'Yeah, we need to 
do this more carefully,'" says Pesetsky. "But he's had seven years to do it 
more carefully and he hasn't."

Critics haven't just accused Everett of inaccurate analysis. He's the sole 
authority on a language that he says changes everything. If he wanted to, they 
suggest, he could lie about his findings without getting caught. Some were 
willing to declare him essentially a fraud. That's what one of the authors of 
the 2009 paper, Andrew Nevins, now at University College London, seems to 
believe. When I requested an interview with Nevins, his reply read, "I may be 
being glib, but it seems you've already analyzed this kind of case!" Below his 
message was a link to an article I had written about a Dutch social 
psychologist who had admitted to fabricating results, including creating data 
from studies that were never conducted. In another e-mail, after declining to 
expand on his apparent accusation, Nevins wrote that the "world does not need 
another article about Dan Everett."

In 2007, Everett heard reports of a letter signed by Cilene Rodrigues, who is 
Brazilian, and who co-wrote the paper with Pesetsky and Nevins, that accuses 
him of racism. According to Everett, he got a call from a source informing him 
that Rodrigues, an honorary research fellow at University College London, had 
sent a letter to the organization in Brazil that grants permission for 
researchers to visit indigenous groups like the Pirahã. He then discovered that 
the organization, called FUNAI, the National Indian Foundation, would no longer 
grant him permission to visit the Pirahã, whom he had known for most of his 
adult life and who remain the focus of his research.

He still hasn't been able to return. Rodrigues would not respond directly to 
questions about whether she had signed such a letter, nor would Nevins. 
Rodrigues forwarded an e-mail from another linguist who has worked in Brazil, 
which speculates that Everett was denied access to the Pirahã because he did 
not obtain the proper permits and flouted the law, accusations Everett calls 
"completely false" and "amazingly nasty lies."

Whatever the reason for his being blocked, the question remains: Is Everett's 
work racist? The accusation goes that because Everett says that the Pirahã do 
not have recursion, and that all human languages supposedly have recursion, 
Everett is asserting that the Pirahã are less than human. Part of this claim is 
based on an online summary, written by a former graduate student of Everett's, 
that quotes traders in Brazil saying the Pirahã "talk like chickens and act 
like monkeys," something Everett himself never said and condemns. The issue is 
sensitive because the Pirahã, who eschew the trappings of modern civilization 
and live the way their forebears lived for thousands of years, are regularly 
denigrated by their neighbors in the region as less than human. The fact that 
Everett is American, not Brazilian, lends the charge added symbolic weight.

When you read Everett's two books about the Pirahã, it is nearly impossible to 
think that he believes they are inferior. In fact, he goes to great lengths not 
to condescend and offers defenses of practices that outsiders would probably 
find repugnant. In one instance he describes, a Pirahã woman died, leaving 
behind a baby that the rest of the tribe thought was too sick to live. Everett 
cared for the infant. One day, while he was away, members of the tribe killed 
the baby, telling him that it was in pain and wanted to die. He cried, but 
didn't condemn, instead defending in the book their seemingly cruel logic.

Likewise, the Pirahã's aversion to learning agriculture, or preserving meat, or 
the fact that they show no interest in producing artwork, is portrayed by 
Everett not as a shortcoming but as evidence of the Pirahã's insistence on 
living in the present. Their nonhierarchical social system seems to Everett 
fair and sensible. He is critical of his own earlier attempts to convert the 
Pirahã to Christianity as a sort of "colonialism of the mind." If anything, 
Everett is more open to a charge of romanticizing the Pirahã culture.

Other critics are more measured but equally suspicious. Mark Baker, a linguist 
at Rutgers University at New Brunswick, who considers himself part of Chomsky's 
camp, mentions Everett's "vested motive" in saying that the Pirahã don't have 
recursion. "We always have to be a little careful when we have one person who 
has researched a language that isn't accessible to other people," Baker says. 
He is dubious of Everett's claims. "I can't believe it's true as described," he 
says.
Chomsky hasn't exactly risen above the fray. He told a Brazilian newspaper that 
Everett was a "charlatan." In the documentary about Everett, Chomsky raises the 
possibility, without saying he believes it, that Everett may have faked his 
results. Behind the scenes, he has been active as well. According to Pesetsky, 
Chomsky asked him to send an e-mail to David Papineau, a professor of 
philosophy at King's College London, who had written a positive, or at least 
not negative, review of Don't Sleep, There Are Snakes. The e-mail complained 
that Papineau had misunderstood recursion and was incorrectly siding with 
Everett. Papineau thought he had done nothing of the sort. "For people outside 
of linguistics, it's rather surprising to find this kind of protection of 
orthodoxy," Papineau says.

And what if the Pirahã don't have recursion? Rather than ferreting out flaws in 
Everett's work as Pesetsky did, Chomsky's preferred response is to say that it 
doesn't matter. In a lecture he gave last October at University College London, 
he referred to Everett's work without mentioning his name, talking about those 
who believed that "exceptions to the generalizations are considered lethal." He 
went on to say that a "rational reaction" to finding such exceptions "isn't to 
say 'Let's throw out the field.'" Universal Grammar permits such exceptions. 
There is no problem. As Pesetsky puts it: "There's nothing that says languages 
without subordinate clauses can't exist."

Except the 2002 paper on which Chomsky's name appears. Pesetsky and others have 
backed away from that paper, arguing not that it was incorrect, but that it was 
"written in an unfortunate way" and that the authors were "trying to make 
certain things comprehensible about linguistics to a larger public, but they 
didn't make it clear that they were simplifying." Some say that Chomsky signed 
his name to the paper but that it was actually written by Marc Hauser, the 
former professor of psychology at Harvard University, who resigned after 
Harvard officials found him guilty of eight counts of research misconduct. (For 
the record, no one has suggested the alleged misconduct affected his work with 
Chomsky.)

Chomsky declined to grant me an interview. Those close to him say he sees 
Everett as seizing on a few stray, perhaps underexplained, lines from that 2002 
paper and distorting them for his own purposes. And the truth, Chomsky has made 
clear, should be apparent to any rational person.
•
Ted Gibson has heard that one before. When Gibson, a professor of cognitive 
sciences at MIT, gave a paper on the topic at a January meeting of the 
Linguistic Society of America, held in Portland, Ore., Pesetsky stood up at the 
end to ask a question. "His first comment was that Chomsky never said that. I 
went back and found the slide," he says. "Whenever I talk about this question 
in front of these people I have to put up the literal quote from Chomsky. Then 
I have to put it up again."

Geoffrey Pullum, a professor of linguistics at the University of Edinburgh, is 
also vexed at how Chomsky and company have, in his view, played rhetorical 
sleight-of-hand to make their case. "They have retreated to such an extreme 
degree that it says really nothing," he says. "If it has a sentence longer than 
three words then they're claiming they were right. If that's what they claim, 
then they weren't claiming anything." Pullum calls this move "grossly dishonest 
and deeply silly."

Everett has been arguing about this for seven years. He says Pirahã undermines 
Universal Grammar. The other side says it doesn't. In an effort to settle the 
dispute, Everett asked Gibson, who holds a joint appointment in linguistics at 
MIT, to look at the data and reach his own conclusions. He didn't provide 
Gibson with data he had collected himself because he knows his critics suspect 
those data have been cooked. Instead he provided him with sentences and stories 
collected by his missionary predecessor. That way, no one could object that it 
was biased.

In the documentary about Everett, handing over the data to Gibson is given 
tremendous narrative importance. Everett is the bearded, safari-hatted field 
researcher boating down a river in the middle of nowhere, talking and eating 
with the natives. Meanwhile, Gibson is the nerd hunched over his keyboard back 
in Cambridge, crunching the data, examining it with his research assistants, to 
determine whether Everett really has discovered something. If you watch the 
documentary, you get the sense that what Gibson has found confirms Everett's 
theory. And that's the story you get from Everett, too. In our first interview, 
he encouraged me to call Gibson. "The evidence supports what I'm saying," he 
told me, noting that he and Gibson had a few minor differences of 
interpretation.

But that's not what Gibson thinks. Some of what he found does support Everett. 
For example, he's confirmed that Pirahã lacks possessive recursion, phrases 
like "my brother's mother's house." Also, there appear to be no conjunctions 
like "and" or "or." In other instances, though, he's found evidence that seems 
to undercut Everett's claims—specifically, when it comes to noun phrases in 
sentences like "His mother, Itaha, spoke."

That is a simple sentence, but inserting the mother's name is a hallmark of 
recursion. Gibson's paper, on which Everett is a co-author, states, "We have 
provided suggestive evidence that Pirahã may have sentences with recursive 
structures."

If that turns out to be true, it would undermine the primary thesis of both of 
Everett's books about the Pirahã. Rather than the hero who spent years in the 
Amazon emerging with evidence that demolished the field's predominant theory, 
Everett would be the descriptive linguist who came back with a couple of books 
full of riveting anecdotes and cataloged a language that is remarkable, but 
hardly changes the game.

Everett only realized during the reporting of this article that Gibson 
disagreed with him so strongly. Until then, he had been saying that the results 
generally supported his theory. "I don't know why he says that," Gibson says. 
"Because it doesn't. He wrote that our work corroborates it. A better word 
would be falsified. Suggestive evidence is against it right now and not for 
it." Though, he points out, the verdict isn't final. "It looks like it is 
recursive," he says. "I wouldn't bet my life on it."
Another researcher, Ray Jackendoff, a linguist at Tufts University, was also 
provided the data and sees it slightly differently. "I think we decided there 
is some embedding but it is of limited depth," he says. "It's not recursive in 
the sense that you can have infinitely deep embedding." Remember that in 
Chomsky's paper, it was the idea that "open-ended" recursion was possible that 
separated human and animal communication. Whether the kind of limited recursion 
Gibson and Jackendoff have noted qualifies depends, like everything else in 
this debate, on the interpretation.

Everett thinks what Gibson has found is not recursion, but rather false starts, 
and he believes further research will back him up. "These are very short, 
extremely limited examples and they almost always are nouns clarifying other 
nouns," he says. "You almost never see anything but that in these cases." And 
he points out that there still doesn't seem to be any evidence of infinite 
recursion. Says Everett: "There simply is no way, even if what I claim to be 
false starts are recursive instead, to say, "'My mother, Susie, you know who I 
mean, you like her, is coming tonight.'"

The field has a history of theoretical disagreements that turn ugly. In the 
book The Linguistic Wars, published in 1995, Randy Allen Harris tells the story 
of another skirmish between Chomsky and a group of insurgent linguists called 
generative semanticists. Chomsky dismissed his opponents' arguments as absurd. 
His opponents accused him of altering his theories when confronted and of 
general arrogance. "Chomsky has the impressive rhetorical talent of offering 
ideas which are at once tentative and fully endorsed, of appearing to take 
the if out of his arguments while nevertheless keeping it safely around," 
writes Harris.

That rhetorical talent was on display in his lecture last October, in which he 
didn't just disagree with other linguists, but treated their arguments as 
ridiculous and a mortal danger to the field. The style seems to be reflected in 
his political activism. Watch his 1969 debate on Firing Lineagainst William F. 
Buckley Jr., available on YouTube, and witness Chomsky tie his famous 
interlocutor in knots. It is a thorough, measured evisceration. Chomsky is 
willing to deploy those formidable skills in linguistic arguments as well.

Everett is far from the only current Chomsky challenger. Recently there's been 
a rise in so-called corpus linguistics, a data-driven method of evaluating a 
language, using computer software to analyze sentences and phrases. The method 
produces detailed information and, for scholars like Gibson, finally provides 
scientific rigor for a field he believes has been mired in never-ending 
theoretical disputes. That, along with the brain-scanning technology that 
linguists are increasingly making use of, may be able to help resolve questions 
about how much of the structure of language is innate and how much is shaped by 
culture.

But Chomsky has little use for that method. In his lecture, he deemed corpus 
linguistics nonscientific, comparing it to doing physics by describing the 
swirl of leaves on a windy day rather than performing experiments. This was 
"just statistical modeling," he said, evidence of a "kind of pathology in the 
cognitive sciences." Referring to brain scans, Chomsky joked that the only way 
to get a grant was to propose an fMRI.

As for Universal Grammar, some are already writing its obituary. Michael 
Tomasello, co-director of the Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary 
Anthropology, has stated flatly that "Universal Grammar is dead." Two 
linguists, Nicholas Evans and Stephen Levinson, published a paper in 2009 
titled "The Myth of Language Universals," arguing that the "claims of Universal 
Grammar ... are either empirically false, unfalsifiable, or misleading in that 
they refer to tendencies rather than strict universals." Pullum has a similar 
take: "There is no Universal Grammar now, not if you take Chomsky seriously 
about the things he says."

Gibson puts it even more harshly. Just as Chomsky doesn't think corpus 
linguistics is science, Gibson doesn't think Universal Grammar is worthwhile. 
"The question is, 'What is it?' How much is built-in and what does it do? There 
are no details," he says. "It's crazy to say it's dead. It was never alive."

Such proclamations have been made before and Chomsky, now 83, has a history of 
outmaneuvering and outlasting his adversaries. Whether Everett will be yet 
another in a long line of would-be debunkers who turn into footnotes remains to 
be seen. "I probably do, despite my best intentions, hope that I turn out to be 
right," he says. "I know that it is not scientific. But I would be a hypocrite 
if I didn't admit it."  


------------------------------
Wittrs mailing list
Wittrs@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxxx
http://undergroundwiki.org/mailman/listinfo/wittrs_undergroundwiki.org

** Note: This message was forwarded to Wittrs by the Editorial Board, so that 
members might enjoy or comment upon it. This is a common practice. If the 
message came from another list or rss feed, the link(s) should appear above. In 
such a situation, the original author may not see your reply. Members of Wittrs 
are encouraged to visit the link(s)that are fed here.

Other related posts: