[lit-ideas] veri similis

  • From: Jlsperanza@xxxxxxx
  • To: lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx
  • Date: Mon, 4 Jun 2012 23:40:34 -0400 (EDT)

vērī sĭmĭlis

In a message dated 5/30/2012  7:10:42 P.M. UTC-02, 
_donalmcevoyuk@xxxxxxxxxxxx  (mailto:donalmcevoyuk@xxxxxxxxxxx) writes: Walter 
recently made a 
remark that  was very complimentary to A.J.  Ayer, to which I suggested a 
useful  
antidote in Popper’s reply to Ayer’s paper for P’s Schilpp volumes. [We 
might  also mention as an antidote Ayer’s misrepresentation of P’s position 
elsewhere,  beginning with Language, Truth and Logic].

Oddly, Alice asks Humpty  Dumpty, "Must a name mean something?". According 
to Sutherland, in "Language and  Lewis Carroll" (Mouton), Carroll is 
reversing Mill's thesis (also Frege's):  proper names have no sense (no 
reference). 
In Wonderland, proper names (like  "Alice") HAVE sense. (Mill's example in 
"System of Logic", that Carroll knew,  was  "London"). Similarly, "Ayer", in 
Wonderland, has TWO senses: one is A.  J. Ayer. The other is a village in 
Switzerland. There is a photograph of a  village in  Switzerland in Ayer (the 
philosopher)'s biography, "Part of my  life". Ayer explains the meaning of 
Ayer.

McEvoy: "Ayer’s paper and P’s  reply might be taken as a useful example of 
the kind of divide that opens up  between those who think on ‘
justificationist’ lines and those who profess not  to." 

I'm not sure "justify" is the proper word (or "just" word, if you  must or 
"-fy"). To justify is to make just. Geary has objected to the idea of  
'justification' ("If 'just'", he writes, "were a matter of _MAKING_ it, then  
Memphis would be in Egypt").

McEvoy: "The justificationist cannot accept  that all knowledge is fallible 
– i.e. that any ‘knowledge-claim’ may be mistaken  – even if this 
fallibilism does not imply that all knowledge  is mistaken.  

Oddly, Geary also objects to the word, "fallibilism". ("Most things are  
fallible, even those which ain't" -- he claims. This was in a polemic 
regarding  the use of subscripts. We were arguing with Geary that most words 
need a  
subscript: "That's nice" should be rewritten as "that's nice-geary" --   
i.e., as uttered by Geary, 'nice' means "nice for Geary". Geary finds the use 
of  subscripts otiose -- "Unless otherwise indicated, or 'shown' but not 
said, alla  Witters, by 'nice' I mean 'nice for me'. Now, in his claim. 
Consider, "Most  things are fallible even those which ain't". It's only, I 
claim, 
the use of  subscripts that resolves the paradox.  The above becomes, "Most 
things are  fallible-geary even those which ain't-speranza" -- and so on. 
Popper never used  subscripts, but perhaps he should.

McEvoy: "Popper’s reply, to “Sir  Alfred Ayer’s contribution”, extends 
over pages 1100-1114 and is divided into  five sections. The first section 
[is] on Verisimilitude"

VERISIMILITUDE  was a concept initiated by Cicero and Quintilian. Those 
Roman philosophers  didn't really know what they were doing. It is like parts 
of America (before the  invention of Harvard) when families would send their 
offspring to OXFORD to get  an education. In Rome, Cicero sent his son to 
ATHENS (hot weather  notwithstanding). Cicero's son was learning PHILOSOPHY in 
the correct lingo,  i.e. Hellenic. And things should have remained  like 
that (where I come  from, and where Grice comes from, Philosophy belongs in
Lit. Hum., and Grice  was more of a classics graduate than a philosophy 
graduate: first in Lit. Hum,  1939, alma mater: classics centre:  Corpus 
Christi -- tutor Hardie).  Instead, Cicero started to create words in some sort 
of 
contrived Roman, such as  'verisimilitude', to render some Greek basic 
notions. Geary has suggested that  the invention of philosophical vocabulary 
can 
be traced back to Aristotle (Geary  thinks he is refuting me by doing this, 
and he means 'refute' as in 'refute').  E.g. Aristotle's use of 'category' 
cannot be traced back to the origins of  philosophy (Thales) because 
Aristotle invented it (not philosophy but  'category'). Now vero- or 
veri-similitude is a silly Roman notion which is hard  to explain 
hellenistically. 
Granted, the Greeks were confused as to  truth.  They saw it as a lady, 
typically: 
Aletheia. Where 'a-' is negation. So, the  
truth is in the unveiling. Years later, Grice, fascinated by von Wright's  
"alethic" will use THIS as paradigm for truth. Now, what is to RESEMBLE or  
simulate (as in -simil-) truth, as in verisimilitude. If Popper were 
SERIOUSLY  responding Ayer he should  have traced the logic of the concepts 
involved  rather than rush to some superficial criticism.

McEvoy: "we might argue  out particular cases – to see, for example, 
whether verisimilitude might  plausibly be deployed in a rational and critical  
way but without its being  underpinned by any justificationist guarantees."

From Etymology  Online:
"verisimilitude c.1600, from Fr. verisimilitude (1540s), from L.  
verisimilitudo "likeness to truth," from veri, genitive of verum,  neut. of  
verus 
"true" (see very) + similis "like, similar" (see similar)." How central  can a 
concept be if it was only introduced in English "c. 1600" ("unlike "sun"",  
Geary writes). Note that the Anglo-Saxons lacked a Tarski theory of truth. 
In  truth, English 'truth' is an abstract noun (hence ending in -th, as in 
depth)  from 'true', where 'true' means 'trust'.  "A trustful friend". The  
Anglo-Saxon idea of 'truth' (Latin verum) is  thus impregnated with  
pscyhological notions. Ayer knew this; Popper didn't the German lingo 
equivalent  
for English 'truth' is itself confused, as has no Graeco-Roman equivalent). 
Note  that the online Stanford avoids the Ciceronian concept of 
'verisimilitude' and  prefers to use the otiose, and slightly wrong,  idea
of 'truthlikeness'.  But '-like' is all full of implicatures: "it's like 
nice", a Valley  girl  says. She means it's NICE, not LIKE nice. So 'like' has 
become  vacuous.  Similarly, "It's like a big nose". Surely a big nose is 
like a big nose. The  ultimate confirmation comes from Clint Eastwood's 
libretto for "Million dollar  baby". The so-called Million dollar baby is 
arguing 
with Clint Eastwood as to  how to clean the gymn. He suggests a substance. 
She  smells it: "Pjjj. This  smells like bleach". Eastwood, calmly: "It is 
bleach. Bleach smells like  bleach".
What Eastwood says (AND shows) is 'true' (not just truthlike) --  Hence 
what is true is also truth-like, hence Popper's otiosities once more   
revealed. Short and Lewis, the organon of Latin in Oxford,  write:
"vērĭsĭmĭlis , vērĭsĭmĭlĭter , and vērĭsĭmĭlĭtūdo , more correctly  
written separately, vērī sĭmĭlis , etc., v. under verus and similis, etc." 
And  they are right. Cicero never claimed to have coined just one  word,
the  odd 'verisimilis'. Rather the two things are separated as in "veri 
similis". ---  Popper didn't know this. And he should, since, among other  
things, he  spoke good German:

"Der Ausdruck veri simile wird von Cicero sowohl in  seinen Reden wie auch 
in seinen philosophischen Schriften zumeist als  rhetorischer  Begriff 
verwendet (griechisch πιιανόν oder εiκός) im Sinn  von
`wahrscheinlich, plausibel'. 

McEvoy: "Some forty years ago, P’s  own proposed definition of 
verisimilitude  was proved defective [by Tichy  and, independently, Miller], 
though this 
 did not mean the concept was  proven irremediably flawed. Subsequent 
search  for a tenable definition has  led to developments that logically refine 
what  is
at stake but no  entirely satisfactory definition has been found as yet.  
Nor perhaps is it  settled what follows from this or what follows if one  is 
not found  (despite the Wittgensteinian author of the Stanford Entry on 
Popper wanting  to suggest the defects of P's definition shipwreck P's 
theory  of  knowledge). The search for a satisfactory account of 
‘verisimilitude’
 has become  a highly technical area beyond the reach of most 
non-specialists. The  implications of this ongoing work is also beyond the 
reach of most."

It's  hardly surprising that Popper's idea of 'veri similitudo' (alla 
Cicero) has  proved defective. As the above source testifies, Cicero perhaps 
should never  have played with the idea -- the Greeks never had a 
concept of 'veri  similitude' (and surely Geary is right when claiming, 
"What's  good
for  the Greeks should be good for us Memphians"). Note that the closest   
idea
in the Greek lexicon is the pair:
πιιανόν -- εiκός
But Popper  typically needs a grander, more pretentious word: not even  ONE 
word, since  it's separated in correct Roman: veri simile. Imagine if  the 
word "God"  were separated like that? Would you say it represents one  big 
important  concept? (cfr. the contrivedness of 'truth-like-ness' that never 
should have  merited in a Greco-Roman dictionary of philosophy but  makes its 
way to  Stanford online!).

McEvoy: "The second section discusses Tarski’s theory  of truth."

It's not surprising that Popper finds a way to fill a few  pages in  his 
volume ("Living philosophers" -- oddly this was reissued once  Popper never 
was -- but a dead one) to his honour. "The idea of a living  philosopher 
came to me," wrote Schlipp, "oddly, when reading Thales, a  notably dead 
one". Grice notes that Tarski's theory of truth is not just wrong  but 
_dead-wrong_ (where 'dead' is implicatural, Grice adds): "A theory of truth  
has 
(as Tarski noted)", Grice writes in "WoW" ("Further notes on logic and  
conversation") to provide not only for occurrences  of 'true' [never mind  
'veri 
similis'] in sentences in which what is  being
spoken of as 'true'  is SPECIFIED [As in Geary, "It is true that it's hot 
today."] but also for  occurrences in sentences in which no specification is 
given." "What Geary said  was true". Grice notes that Tarski fails to 
provide a proper pragmatic  analysis  of non-specified approaches to true. If 
'true' is related to  'commitment' (as in trust -- in God we trust. Note the 
cognateness, true-trust),  then "I do not think", Grice observes, "I should be 
PROPERLY regarded as having  _committed_ myself to the content of [Geary's] 
statement, merely in virtue of  having said that it was 'true'. When to my 
surprise, I learn that [Geary]  actually said ["2 + 2 = 5" -- a blatant 
falsehood, or  "Memphis is not the  capital of Egypt"], I say, perhaps, "Well, 
I 
was wrong -- [what Geary said was  not true], but NOT, "I withdraw that, or 
"I withdraw my commitment to that". I  never was committed to it."

McEvoy: "The third concerns The Verification  of Theories." 

If "veri simile" was an otiose concept, so was Popper's  claim to  infame: 
veri-fy. If for each adjective (think 'smooth') we would  need a 
corresponding -fy verb to give prestige to it, we would have more words  than 
we 
need. Hence Popper's joke about 'falsi-fy'.

McEvoy: ""there  is a sense in which  we shall after all have a general 
criterion for  recognizing empirical 
truth.’""

ENTER EMPIRICAL TRUTH. Popper just  sticks to the phrase, complex, 
typically, rather than analyse bit by bit. What  do we mean  'empirical'? 
"Empiricism revisited", indeed. If Popper had  proceeded analytically he would 
not 
have delivered such simplicities as he  did.

McEvoy: "“By ‘empirical truth’ Ayer means, especially, the truth  of  
scientific
theories"

If Popper had an idea of how rooted  Empiricism was in Oxford -- if he  had 
an idea of the progress of the early  philosophies of Ayer -- and  Grice -- 
he would have known that Ayer's  "Problems of knowledge" was considered  an 
important attempt, by an English  Oxford philosopher -- originally --  to 
revisit the truth about Hume, that  the members of Vienna Circle  without 
Anglo-Saxon blood in their veins,  could not have cared less about.  Hume was 
the truly empiricist philosopher  and he was following Locke, who was  
refuting
Descartes. Empereia, is  the Greek notion. To think, as Popper 
simplistically does, that Ayer means  'scientific' by 'empirical' only goes to 
show  how 
obsessed Popper is with  'winning' (or trying to win) an argument  rather 
than engage with his  interlocutor. In this case, it is lack of manners,  too,
seeing that it  was a contribution to a sort of festchrift, "library of 
living philosophers"  ("The idea came to me that while Thales, a dead 
philosopher, could not reply to  critics, a living philosopher, if paid, would. 
Hence the substantial sum we  gave Popper for his rather rude replies -- in 
some sort
of non-colloquial  English").

McEvoy: "; and the statement just quoted implies that, given  an empirical  
method to decide on the truth or falsity of what I in Logik  der Forschung  
called ‘ basic statements’ ... ‘Finding a counterexample  proves the 
statement  false, but failing to find one does not prove it  true….’"

"Fail to be false" is one of the most otiose otiosities. Grice  noted  
this: "I fail to be a girl", Grice once argued.
The alleged  counterexample was: "But you never tried". That is: in common 
parlance, "fail"  is overused. Typicaly, failures  are failures with regard 
to this or that  dimension. Hence, Popper is  sticking
with a colloquialism in Ayer (and  the English language -- "fail to  find a 
falsity") and missing the  idiomatic point.

McEvoy: "If it sounds so, it is because Ayer is a trifle  indistinct about 
what set of basic statements is ‘some set of basic  statements’."

Ayer, unlike Popper, knew what Ayer was writing about. In  the early  days 
of Oxford analytic philosophy, they were concerned with  Paul, "Is there  a 
problem about sense data?". They were arguing,  seriously, as per  Berlin, 
in "Concepts and Categories" about the ultimate  idea of a 'basic' (so 
mis-called) concept like a sense datum like "red". The  idea was NEVER 
scientific. 
While Cambridge philosophers THINK They Do, Oxonian  philosophers  DEFINE 
theirselves by their disrespect for science. What does  science tell us
about 'red'? Nothing that someone who knows his Locke needs  or cares to  
learn!

McEvoy: " empirical omniscience involves  basic  omniscience.""

Seeing that Ayer does not use 'science'  seriously, to stick to yet another 
pretentious label, as is Popper's wont,  'omni-science' is irrisory  (or 
laughable-geary if you must). Note that in  Ciceronian Roman, scio, as in 
science, means 'know' a concept that the Greeks  avoided, "Know thyself" (and 
fail). Now, "scio" is a factive in Roman: "I know  it". But science, as  
Popper misunderstood it, is all about not really  being sure. Instead of
providing his own falsificatory approach to science,  Popper should have 
started by concentrating on the fact that what he is dealing  with is NOT  
'scientia' as the Romans knew it. Scientia is never wrong  never mind 
falsifiable. So: "I know but I am wrong" -- is one of the  catastrophes of 
Graeco-Roman philosophy. If Popper 
had been more  knowledgeable of the history of the discipline he was 
playing in, he would never  have written a book on "Objective knowledge"!

McEvoy:"‘All swans are  white’" "Einstein’s denial is just as 
metaphysical, or almost as  metaphysical,
because nothing observable follows from it."

Popper's  addition of 'metaphysical' can only confuse. As Grice notes  in 
an  interesting essay, "Actions and Events": Philosophy is all about 
hypostasis;  science is about mere hypothesis". Grice is arguing that 
the distinction,  often made by German-speaking philosophers -- and by the 
confused Ayer at one  point -- between metaphysic (nonsense) and scientific 
(sense) is itself  nonsense. Hypostasis and hypothesis are ways to approach  
reality, and  hypostasis is actually a better, deeper grasp. Nothing 
'metaphysical'
about  it.

McEvoy: "'All swans are white’ only “may” be a case where the absence  of 
any
counterexample is a sufficient condition of truth. 

There are  of course black swans: Black Swan. Conservation status. Least 
Concern (IUCN  3.1)[1]. Scientific classification. Kingdom: Animalia. Phylum: 
Chordata. Class:  Aves. Order: Anseriformes. Family: Anatidae
Subfamily: Anserinae. Tribe:  Cygnini. Genus: Cygnus. Species: Cygnus 
atratus
Binomial name: Cygnus atratus  (Latham, 1790). Subspecies: Cygnus atratus 
atratus. Black Swan
†C. a.  sumnerensis. New Zealand Swan (extinct). Synonyms: Anas atrata 
Latham, 1790,  Chenopis atratus."

It's different with 'ravens' (Reichenbach, cited by  Grice -- and his 
famous counterexample): All ravens are black. An albino white  raven  does not 
COU
NT -- genetically. J. L. Austin, a distant 'friend' with  Grice, 
argues in "How to do things with words" that "all" in "All swans are  
white" is hyperbolic and parents know that. "France is hexagonal" is his other  
example of hyperbole that parents can use. "Surely, the presence of this or 
that  non-white swan in areas unknown to the Roman empire is no refutation   
of
the early bird systematics". (I draw material here from Grice's example of  
hyperbole in "Logic and Conversation: "Every nice girl loves a sailor" -- 
cfr.  "All swans are white"). 

McEvoy: " Taken as a UL,  the absence of a  counterexample is not a 
sufficient but only a necessary 
condition of the  truth of ‘All swans are white’. But none of this rescues 
Ayer’s views from P’s  logical demolition."

It was in 1790 that Latham first saw what he called  "a black swan".  In 
those days, Latin was the lingo, so he said he saw an  "anas atrata 
Lathamiensis". The point was brought back to London, where there  was
discussion as to Cicero's use of 'cygnus'. In no passage was 'albus'  
related to  'cygnus' tautologically, so it was concluded that indeed what  
Latham 
saw was a black 'swan', rather than another bird. The confirmation  was  
"philological". ("Had Cicero made a point about 'cygnus' HAVING to be  white 
we would have  been
in deep trouble", professor Middleton wrote --  "Proceedings of the  London 
Zoological Society", Zoological Gardens,  Kew).

McEvoy: "the acceptance or rejection of [basic statements] is   a matter 
for something like the scientific jury – the scientific community   (which may 
or may not come to an agreement).”"

Since Popper is being  oversimplistic in his exegesis of the  complexities 
Ayer (and the early  Grice) saw in 'basic' as per sense-datum  EMPIRICAL 
content of subjectivity  (totally unrelated to 'science' as Popper 
never knew it) it's no wonder he  yet agains is only finding an excuse to 
fill a few  more
pages for his  own festschrift.

McEvoy: "There is a final section on Subjective  Experience and Linguistic 
Formulation, where P addresses “What is the  fundamental difference between 
Ayer and
myself?”; but we may be spared this  story. (For now.)"

The fundamental difference between Ayer and Popper is  that while both  are 
German in origin (note the village in Switzerland,  called "Ayer")  there 
is no Swiss village called "Popper". Popper knew this  and was envious.

Speranza

---
References:
•Aronson, J.,  1997, "Truth, Verisimilitude, and Natural Kinds",
Philosophical Papers, 26:  71-104.
•Barnes, E., •–––, 1991, "Beyond Verisimilitude: A Linguistically  
Invariant Basis
for Scientific Progress", Synthese, 88: 309-339.
•–––,  1995, "Truthlikeness, Translation, and Approximate Causal
Explanation",  Philosophy of Science, 62/2: 15-226.
•Brink, C., & Heidema, J., 1987, "A  verisimilar ordering of theories
phrased in a propositional language", The  British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science, 38: 533-549.
•Britton, T.,  2004, "The problem of verisimilitude and counting 
partially
identical  properties", Synthese, 141: 77–95.
•Britz, K., and Brink, C., 1995,  "Computing verisimilitude", Notre 
Dame Journal of Formal Logic, 36/2:  30-43.
.
•Burger, I. C., in Confirmation, Empirical Progress, and  Truth
Approximation,
Amsterdam, New York: Rodopi, pp. 459–488.
•Cohen,  L.J., •–––, 1987, "Verisimilitude and legisimilitude", in 
Kuipers 1987a, 
pp.  129-45.
•Gerla, G., 1992, "Distances, diameters and verisimilitude of  
theories", Archive for mathematical Logic, 31/6: 407-14.
•Harris, J.,  1974, "Popper's definition of ‘Verisimilitude’", The
British Journal for the  Philosophy of Science, 25: 160-166.
•Hilpinen, R., 1976, "Approximate truth  and truthlikeness" in 
Przelecki,
et al. (eds.), Formal Methods in the  Methodology of the Empirical
Sciences, Dordrecht: Reidel, 19-42
•Kieseppa,  I.A., 1996, Truthlikeness for Multidimensional, 
Quantitative
Cognitive  Problems, Dordrecht: Kluwer.
•–––, 1996, "Truthlikeness for Hypotheses  Expressed in Terms of n
Quantitative Variables", Journal of Philosophical  Logic, 25: 109-134.
•–––, 1996, "On the Aim of the Theory of Verisimilitude",  Synthese,
107:
421-438
•Kuipers, T. A. F. (ed.), 1987a, What is  closer-to-the-truth? A 
parade of
approaches to truthlikeness (Poznan  Studies in the Philosophy of the
Sciences and the Humanities, Volume 10),  Amsterdam: Rodopi.
•–––, 1987b, "A structuralist approach to truthlikeness",  in Kuipers 
1987a, pp. 79-99.
•–––, 1987c, "Truthlikeness of stratified  theories", in Kuipers  1987a, 
pp. 177-186.
•Miller, D., 1972, "The  Truth-likeness of Truthlikeness", Analysis, 
33/2:
50-55.
•–––, 1974a,  "Popper's Qualitative Theory of Verisimilitude", The 
British Journal for the  Philosophy of Science, 25: 166-177.
•–––, 1976, "Verisimilitude Redeflated",  The British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science, 27/4: 363-381.
•–––,  1982, "Truth, Truthlikeness, Approximate Truth", Fundamenta
Scientiae, 3/1:  93-101
•Niiniluoto, I., 1977, "On the Truthlikeness of Generalizations’,  in
Butts et al. (eds.), Basic Problems in Methodology and  Linguistics,
Dordrecht:
Reidel, pp. 121-147.
•–––, 1978a,  "Truthlikeness: Comments on Recent Discussion", 
Synthese,
38:  281-329.
•–––, 1978b, "Verisimilitude, Theory-Change, and Scientific  
Progress",
in I. Niiniluoto et al. (eds.), The Logic and Epistemology of  
Scientific
Change, Acta Philosophica Fennica,, 30/2-4, Amsterdam:  North-Holland, 
pp.
243-264.
•–––, 1979a, "Truthlikeness in First-Order  Languages", in I. 
Niiniluoto
et al. (eds.), Essays on Mathematical and  Philosophical Logic, 
Dordrecht:

Reidel, pp. 437-458.
•–––, 1979b,  "Degrees of Truthlikeness: From Singular Sentences to
Generalizations", The  British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 
30:
371-376.
•–––,  1982a, "Scientific Progress", Synthese, 45/3: 427-462.
•–––, 1982b, "What  Shall We Do With Verisimilitude?", Philosophy of
Science, 49:  181-197.
•–––, 1983, "Verisimilitude vs. Legisimilitude", Studia  Logica,
XLII/2-3: 315-329.
•–––, 1986, "Truthlikeness and Bayesian  Estimation", Synthese, 67:
321-346.
•–––, 1987a, "How to Define  Verisimilitude", in Kuipers 1987a, pp.
11-23.
•–––, 1987b, "Verisimilitude  with Indefinite Truth", in Kuipers 
1987a,
pp. 187-195.
•–––, 1987c,  Truthlikeness, Dordrecht: Reidel.
•–––. "Reference Invariance and  Truthlikeness", in Philosophy of
Science
64 (1997), pp. 546-554.
•–––,  1998, "Survey Article: Verisimilitude: The Third Period", in 
The
British  Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 49: 1-29.
•–––, 1999, Critical  Scientific Realism, Oxford: Clarendon.
•Oddie, G., 1978, "Verisimilitude and  distance in logical space", 
Acta
Philosophica Fennica, 30/2-4:  227-243.
•–––, 1981, "Verisimilitude reviewed", The British Journal for  the
Philosophy of Science, 32: 237-65.
•–––, 1982, "Cohen on  verisimilitude and natural necessity", 
Synthese,
51: 355-79.
•–––,  1986a, Likeness to Truth, (Western Ontario Series in  Philosophy
of
Science), Dordrecht: Reidel.
•–––, 1986b, "The poverty of  the Popperian program for 
truthlikeness",
Philosophy of Science, 53/2:  163-78.
•–––, 1987a, "The picture theory of truthlikeness", in Kuipers  1987a,
pp. 25-46.
•–––. 1987b, "Truthlikeness and the convexity of  propositions" in 
What
is Closer-to-the-Truth?, T. Kuipers (ed.),  Amsterdam: Rodopi, pp. 
197-217.
•–––, 1990, "Verisimilitude by power  relations", British Journal for
the Philosophy of Science, 41:  129-35.
•–––, 1997a, "Truthlikeness" in D. Borchert (ed.), The Encyclopedia  
of Philosophy Supplement, New York: Macmillan, pp. 574-6.
•–––. 1997b,  "Conditionalization, cogency and cognitive value" The
British Journal for the  Philosophy of Science, 48: 533-41.
•–––, 2001, "Truth, Verification,  Confirmation, Verisimilitude", in
N.J. Smelser et al. (eds.), International  Encyclopedia of the Social and
Behavioral Sciences, Oxford:  Elselvier.
•–––, 2007, "Truthlikeness and Value", in Festschrift for  Illkka
Niiniluoto, College Publications: London, forthcoming.
•Pearce, D.,  1983, "Truthlikeness and translation: a comment on 
Oddie",
The British  Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 34: 380-5.
•Popper, K. R., 1963,  Conjectures and Refutations, London: Routledge.
•–––, 1976, "A note on  verisimilitude", The British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science, 27/2:  147-159.
•Rosencrantz, R., 1975, "Truthlikeness: comments on David  Miller",
Synthese, 30/1-2: 193-7.
•Ryan, M. and P.Y. Schobens, 1995,  "Belief revision and 
verisimilitude",
Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic,  36: 15-29.
•Schurz, G., and Weingartner, P., 1987, "Verisimilitude defined  by
relevant consequence-elements", in Kuipers 1987a, pp. 47-77.
•Tichý,  P., 1974, "On Popper's definitions of verisimilitude", The
British
Journal  for the Philosophy of Science, 25: 155-160.
•–––, 1976, "Verisimilitude  Redefined", The British Journal for the
Philosophy of Science, 27:  25-42.
•–––, 1978, "Verisimilitude Revisited" Synthese, 38:  175-196.
•Tooley, M., 1977, "The Nature of Laws", Canadian Journal of  
Philosophy,
7: 667-698.
•Urbach, P., 1983, "Intimations of similarity:  the shaky basis of
verisimilitude", The British Journal for the Philosophy of  Science, 
34:
166-75.
•Vetter, H., 1977, "A new concept of  verisimilitude", Theory and
Decision,
8: 369-75.
•Volpe, G., 1995, "A  semantic approach to comparative 
verisimilitude", The
British Journal for  the Philosophy of Science, 46: 563-82.
•Weston, T., 1992, "Approximate truth  and scientific realism", 
Philosophy
of Science, 59: 53-74.
•Zamora  Bonilla, J. P., 1992, "Truthlikeness Without Truth: A
Methodological  Approach", Synthese, 93: 343–72.
•–––, 1996, "Verisimilitude, Structuralism  and Scientific Progress",
Erkenntnis, 44: 25–47.
•–––, 2000,  "Truthlikeness, Rationality and Scientific Method",
Synthese, 122:  321-335.
•–––, 2002, "Verisimilitude and the Dynamics of Scientific  Research
Programmes", Journal for the General Philosophy of Science, 33:  
349-368
•Zwart, S. D., 2001, Refined Verisimilitude, Dordrecht:  Kluwer.
•Zwart, S. D., and M. Franssen, 2007, "An impossibility theorem  for
verisimilitude", Synthese, forthcoming in print.  

------------------------------------------------------------------
To change your Lit-Ideas settings (subscribe/unsub, vacation on/off,
digest on/off), visit www.andreas.com/faq-lit-ideas.html

Other related posts:

  • » [lit-ideas] veri similis - Jlsperanza