[Wittrs] Re: some helpful guidelines for reading Wittgenstein's philo...

  • From: Glen Sizemore <gmsizemore2@xxxxxxxxx>
  • To: Wittrs@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxx
  • Date: Sun, 9 Aug 2009 10:57:19 -0700 (PDT)

--- On Sun, 8/9/09, Glen Sizemore <gmsizemore2@xxxxxxxxx> wrote:


From: Glen Sizemore <gmsizemore2@xxxxxxxxx>
Subject: Re: [Wittrs] Re: some helpful guidelines for reading Wittgenstein's 
philo...
To: Wittrs@xxxxxxxxxxxxxxx
Date: Sunday, August 9, 2009, 1:12 PM


  

The reply below was accidentally sent, so I will continue with what I was 
saying...

--- On Sat, 8/8/09, Stuart W. Mirsky <SWMirsky@aol. com> wrote:

From: Stuart W. Mirsky <SWMirsky@aol. com>
Subject: [Wittrs] Re: some helpful guidelines for reading Wittgenstein' s 
philo...
To: Wittrs@yahoogroups. com
Date: Saturday, August 8, 2009, 10:02 PM

--- In Wittrs@yahoogroups. com, "gerardoprim" <gerardoprim@ ...> wrote:
>
> (Stuart) When I was driving up through the Carolinas and suddenly realized 
> the meaning of a sign that had initially seemed incomprehensible to me, I 
> suddenly had certain images in my mind. There were no behavioral changes. I 
> just kept driving. (The wiper blades and lights were already on.) But at one 
> point I didn't understand and then I did. What occurred is not explainable as 
> behavior unless you so broaden the term of "behavior" as to make it 
> meaningless.
> (Gerardo) Why do you say that the broader concept of behavior would be 
> "meaningless" ? It will be meaningful as long as it´s part of a language 
> game, and new language-games come into existence all the time (PI 23). Also, 
> cognitive science has changed the traditional grammar of many concepts (e.g. 
> "representation" , "cognition", "computation" ), and possibly you wouldn´t 
> say those concepts became "meaningless" . The narrower meaning of behavior is 
> "publicly observable activity", the broader meaning includes also "privately 
> observed activity". There´re many similarities that allow the extension of 
> the concept, e.g. there´s a degree of public observability (e.g. talk aloud, 
> talk whispering, talk privately to ourselves), conditioning principles can be 
> applied to both overt and covert activities, covert activities are previously 
> learned as overt behavior (covert reading comes from previous overt reading, 
> mental math calculation comes from previous overt
math calculations, imagery comes from previous perception, self-talk comes from 
previous overt talk), etc. You can say "I don´t like it" or "I´d prefer another 
word", but you cannot say it´s "meaningless" .
> 
> Regards,
> Gerardo.
>

SWM: Yes, you're right Gerardo. It has meaning the way you put it. But it still 
fails a test that I think is important here. Terms do change all the time. 
Language isn't static though it usually changes fairly slowly. However it is 
possible to so broaden what we mean by a term as to extract it from its 
original uses. If "behavior" means what is observable in a being capable of 
acting (though we can and do talk of the behavior of rocks and gases, etc. 
though that is irrelevant to behaviorist psychology) then to add in "and I also 
mean all the mental events the being is having that prompt him/her/it to act or 
that accompany the said acts or that may presage the entity's acting under 
certain conditions (when a response is called for), then it no longer is about 
the acts of the entity under study. It is now about the very things the usual 
idea of behavior does not apply to.

GS: I find this argument somewhat bizarre. First, though, you slipped up above 
when you said "If 'behavior' means what is observable in a being capable of 
acting... [then private events are outside of this definition], " you must have 
meant "If 'behavior' means what is PUBLICLY observable in a being capable of 
acting..." Skinner's behaviorism (radical behaviorism) holds that the sorts of 
events being called "private events" are, in fact, observable, but they are 
observable only to the behaving individual. This, incidentally, does NOT 
include much of what is called "mental" since much of what is called "mental" 
is not observable even to the behaving individual! But more importantly, the 
argument you use has the curious effect of cutting off a behavioristic account 
of certain phenomena. You are, in effect, saying that if behaviorism attempts 
to deal with certain issues it ceases to be behaviorism, and thus behaviorism 
can have no account of certain
phenomena! But behaviorism is the view that behavior is the proper subject 
matter of psychology, and that it can be a complete view, leaving nothing out. 
It holds that what is "spected" in introspection IS behavior (or, perhaps, 
stimuli generated by behavior). Hence the term "radical behaviorism, " where 
"radical" means "thoroughgoing. " Unlike Watsonian behaviorism (I make a 
distinction between Watsonian and methodological behaviorim), which denies the 
existence of "mental imagery*," and methodological behaviorism, which 
acknowledges the role of subjectivity but rules it out of scientific 
consideration, radical behaviorism argues that what is observed in 
introspection IS behavior. Thus, rather than being a sort of concession to 
mentalism, what one gets is a kind of "super behaviorism" (i.e. RADICAL 
behaviorism) . Radical behaviorism is MORE behavioristic than Watsonian or 
methodological behaviorism - especially methodoilogical behaviorism which is, in
fact almost indistinguishable from mentalism. As Gerardo has pointed out (and 
he has done an excellent job) is that in a behavioristic account, private 
behavior STILL follows the laws of overt behavior. Also, as he has pointed out 
(as have I), there are a few things that suggest the cogency of this position: 
first, there is the simple fact of private talking (or reading silently, for 
example). Do you really want to argue that when we read silently we are not 
behaving? That the eye movements are the only thing that is behavior and what 
we "hear" silently is NOT behavior? Second, related to this, is that the energy 
level of behavior is a differentiable property of behavior. That is, by 
arranging contingencies of reinforcement (the main explanatory principle of 
radical behaviorism) one can produce response classes where the energy level is 
quite low. We can't, of course, arrange contingencies based on complete 
non-observability (hence the similarity to to
Wittgenstein' s treatment of the impossibility of a "private language"). But 
the point is that behavior can occur with a range of energy levels - why can't 
it occur at a level that renders it unobservable to anyone but the behaving 
individual? Indeed, the cultural evolution of "silent reading" seems to 
constitute just such an occurrence. The historical record indicates that, in 
fact, there was a period of time when "silent reading" did not occur. It has 
been suggested that it (silent reading) arose after the advent of libraries. 
When there are a room full of people reading different texts out loud, reading 
accurately is difficult. This lead to a situation that fostered ever less 
energetic vocal behavior until the public aspects were removed by differential 
contingencies of punishment. In some people, remnants of "reading out loud" 
remain; it is sometimes difficult to get children to read silently without 
"moving their lips." Finally, the most important
aspect of treating private events as behavior stems from the fact (and this is 
not unrelated to my previous points) that, even when unobservable, the 
hypothesized behavior comes about because of contingencies. That is, the total 
behavioral episode (and I will give an example immediately below) is best, 
given a respect for parsimony, viewed as behavior. One of my favorite examples 
of this is the "directed forgetting" literature with pigeons. I will describe 
this phenomenon, but I am not going to try to describe specific experiments, 
though my description will closely parallel experiments that have been done. 
This will be somewhat long-winded. Consider delayed match-to-sample experiments 
(DMTS). In such experiments, the center key (in operant experiments with 
pigeons, they often peck a plastic strip that is mounted behind a circular hole 
in the operant chamber - the palstic is translucent, and when a colored light 
is turned on behind them, the key
appears as a colored circle) is transilluminated with a color, and there are at 
least two different colors used. At he beginning of a trial the center key (of 
three horizontally- arranged keys) is, say illuminated "red." The pigeon pecks 
this key and the light is turned off. After some delay (on the order of 
seconds), the two "side keys" are illuminated. One key is the same color as the 
now extinguished "sample" and the other is some other color. If the pigeon 
pecks the red key, food is delivered, if it pecks the "wrong" key, no food is 
delivered and there is often a "blackout" for some period of time (i.e., 
negative punishment). If the delay is not too long between the sample and the 
choice stimuli (10 s is often too long for a pigeon), the pigeon will peck the 
"correct" key above chance levels. If the delay is on the order of a few 
seconds, the accuracy can be quite high. This, of course, is often held to be 
an animal model of "working memory." One of
the first things to notice (though this is not my main point) is that in order 
to get pigeons to respond correctly at longer delays, the delay must be 
gradually lengthened. One can not just go from a zero s delay to a four s 
delay. That is, the pigeon must be trained, and the training involves gradually 
changing the contingencies of reinforcement, just as is done when behavior is 
trained in other circumstances. But, once the pigeon is trained, one can do 
something interesting; one can add a stimulus, say a tone. On trials where the 
tone is present, the trial no longer ends with the usual stimuli. Instead, for 
example, both side keys can be illuminated with a white light, and pecking 
either key results in reinforcement. Or, the trial may simply end with a 
blackout. An interesting thing happens when one does this. If one turns on the 
tone, but presents the choice stimuli anyway (clever, huh), the pigeon's 
accuracy falls to 50% (i.e., chance levels). It
does not remember what color the sample was, even at delays that it usually 
"handles" quite well. What is the interpretation of this effect? I think the 
parsimonious answer is this: in DMTS the animal learns to behave in some 
particular SUBTLE way when the sample is presented. This SUBTLE behavior 
continues through the "retention interval" and it is this behavior that 
discriminatively controls the choice response. When the tone is presented, the 
behavior that occurs during the retention interval is not reinforced (either 
because no food can be obtained, or because the reinforced response is 
irrelevant to the sample), and it undergoes extinction, but it is only 
extinguished in the presence of the tone. Now, what is compelling here, is that 
what the pigeon does during the retention interval (if, indeed, it is DOING 
something) is not easily observed, and efforts to find "mediating behavior" has 
often failed. Interestingly, in the few cases where the
mediating behavior IS easily observed (like, the pigeon turns around to the 
left when the sample was red, and turns to the right when it was green), there 
is no "forgetting function!" But the main point is that, even though the 
mediating behavior cannot be observed publicly, [this is where I left off], the 
"alleged behavior" adheres to the same laws as publicly-observable behavior. A 
stimulus is presented that "signals" that the behavior will go unreinforced, 
and the behavior undergoes extinction. When the choice stimuli are presented 
anyway, accuracy falls to chance levels. If, whatever is going on is regarded 
as "mental," the fact is that the this "mental" DOING obeys the same laws as 
observable behavior. In order to see this clearly, let's say that we conducted 
a different experiment. Say we had two keys mounted below the three keys in the 
experiment I just described. In this experiment, the pigeon is trained 
explicitly to peck the lowest left-hand
 key when the sample is red, and the lower right-hand key when the sample is 
green. At the end of the "retention interval," the original side keys are 
illuminated. It is worth noting that there would be no appreciable forgetting 
function (and I'll discuss the significance of this later - not necessarily in 
this post since it is already long). Here, it is obvious that the mediating 
behavior is, in fact, behavior. If we now introduce the tone "telling the 
pigeon that pecking the lower keys will go unreinforced," pecking those keys 
will cease, and the probe trials will result in chance levels of responding. 
The main point here is that the same operations that result in the extinction 
of explicitly-trained mediating behavior also result in the extinction of the 
alleged private behavior that is not explicitly trained and not easily 
observed. One may insist that the "mental" activity that is not publicly 
observable is of a different sort from the
 publicly-observable mediating behavior, but one does so at the expense of the 
more parsimonious, non-dulistic interpretation.               

*Watson argued that "thinking" was "subvocal speech," so he did not deny all 
subjectivity.

SWM; If behavioral pyschology includes our mental events (ideas, thoughts, 
feelings, beliefs, images, logical connections, etc.) then how can we continue 
to call it behavioral? 

GS: I hope I have given an answer to this question. Whatever the animal is 
doing in the retention interval is not observable, but it is affected in the 
same way as behavior in the second sort of experiment. No? One might ask "How 
can we not call it behavior?" 

SWM: Now I take it you and, perhaps, Glen are arguing that that is precisely 
what Skinner really meant (or what his followers now mean) and as I have said I 
am no expert on psychology or behaviorism or Skinner so I don't want to be seen 
here as passing judgment on that claim. Certainly, I must reiterate, I do NOT 
believe that any real behaviorists ever really thought they don't have the 
kinds of mental events I've described here despite how many of their claims 
might sound. So it is possible that your interpretation is correct and they do 
mean more by "behavior" than merely overt (observable) actions.

But if THAT is the case it looks to me that they are confused because they are 
so redefining "behavior" as to make it no longer about behavior but about all 
the things most of us usually recognize as being other than behavior. Perhaps 
this debate is really just about terms and meanings though?

GS: Yes, the debate is partly about meanings. But why? I assert that, in part, 
the reason is that one must abandon the comfortable assertion that behaviorism 
cannot account for phenomena that are interesting. And, ironically, when 
behaviorists do account for such phenomena, it is claimed that it is "not 
really behaviorism." What utter nonsense! 

Cordially,
Glen

Other related posts: