[lit-ideas] Re: You be the judge/What is wrong with this picture?

  • From: Jlsperanza@xxxxxxx
  • To: lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx
  • Date: Sun, 8 Dec 2013 20:11:50 -0500 (EST)

I know I'm not replying McEvoy's answers!, but  found some more enlightment 
from a previous post in Lit-Ideas, which I comment  below. 

I consider a few keywords that may apply: CONSEQUENTIALISM,  relativism, 
and whether Toulmin is right in thinking legalistic argumentation as  the 
model for any argumentation  simpliciter.

Cheers,

Speranza

----

McEvoy:

"To  think on the right lines, focus on two things: (1) what will be effect 
of the  result in cases, like Pilcher, where there is a trust of a house 
that is sold,  and (2) what will be the effect of the result in cases (the 
vast majority) where  there is no trust of a house that is sold? There. Said 
it. The solution is  there, in the answers to (1) and (2). So what are the 
answers - what would be  the effects? And what does this consequential 
reasoning tell us as to what  should be the rule here and therefore the result?"

Well, I append below  some material  from


//www.freelists.org/post/lit-ideas/Popperian-Jurisprudence-Amended

as  I comment on it.

McEvoy:

"the case [Pilcher v Rawlins] that (in  English law) ... [-] a
buyer of a house in good faith from a dishonest  trustee takes ownership 
free of
the trust [-]"

"there is scant  explanation for the decision at all."

"In the Pilcher v Rawlins judgment,  the rule is not located within a 
framework of comparable rules."

"Still  less is the decision explained as a result of weighing up the 
consequences of  deciding it
one way or another"

"Instead, we
find ... that the  plaintiff [the beneficiary of the trust
who was suing to get the house back]  was "non-suited"".

"Now what does this tell us (jurisprudentially  speaking)?"

"What Pilcher v Rawlins does
illustrate is why it is very  problematic ... to
think we can straightforwardly 'read off' the underlying  legal thinking 
from
'what judges say'. 

---- This is a bit of an  implicature too.

Compare Grice:

It is very problematic to think we  can straightforwardly 'read off' 
(BETWEEN THE LINES', the implicature) [of] the  underlying ... thinking from 
what 
an utterer says!?

---

"Sometimes  'what judges say' may be a
reliable guide to the underlying thinking that  underpins the decision, but
sometimes it may be an unreliable and even  misleading guide."

And one wonders if one should wonder. I think it is  more important to 
emphasise what a judge says than what a judge THINKS. After  all, is not the 
evidence we have for someone THINKS what that someone  SAYS?

---

"Sometimes 'what
judges say' cannot be taken at face  value - indeed, it is_ always open to
argument_ to what extent 'what judges  say' can be taken at face value in 
any
particular case."

This may  apply to any utterance whatsoever.

I say "It is raining". 

Should  we taken, to use Geary's phrase, "at face value"?

Perhaps the utterer is  IMPLICATING something. And if we challenge with the 
implicature ("Are you  suggesting this is an excuse NOT to go to the 
cinema?") he may go on to produce  a dis- or counter-implicature ("On the 
contrary: rainy days ARE ideal cinema  days"). 


McEvoy:

"the decision that "it
would not be  unconscionable for the honest buyer to keep the house" could
be disputed by  saying 'How can the buyer keep in good conscience what he
discovers was  subject to a trust?'"

I think it is for reasons like these that Toulmin  thought of lawyer's 
argumentation to be the model for argumentation simpliciter,  rather than the 
axiomatic approach favoured by philosophers or logicians of more  Euclidean 
tendencies?

It seems to be an argument for relativism,  too?


McEvoy:

a

"court engages not merely in determining  the limits of its own 
jurisdiction ... but in solving
certain kinds of  problem."

"This helps explain why some study of the effects of the law  may be 
relevant to
understanding the law even though that study played no  part in the process 
by
which that law was arrived at."

This seems like  a justification of moral consequentialism that (I think) 
Kant  detested.



McEvoy:

"One tutor's book, based on his  doctoral
thesis, was an attempt to show the role of "policy" in  judicial
decision-making, by way of reading off the role of "policy"  in
various judicial decisions."

"This 'reading off', we were  repeatedly informed,
amounted to an "empirical critique" of rival  jurisprudential views."

"Aside from the misconceived and pretentious use  of "empirical" (for
how was this 'reading off' falsifiable by observation?),  what the book 
lacked
was some kind of argument or analysis that explained how  we move from 'what
judges say [when giving judgment]' to the underlying  jurisprudence."

"Another tutor's book was littered with specious and  spurious claims of 
which
the following is an example, but requires some  scene-setting."

"At common law, if
I steal your painting and sell it  to another who buys in good faith, that 
buyer
does not get a good title - you  can sue the buyer to get your painting 
back."

"But property held under  trust is different"

"If I hold ownership of a house as a
trustee for  you [with my name on the deeds as the legal owner], and I sell 
the
house to  another who buys the deeds in good faith and without knowing my  
legal
ownership is subject to a trust [which trust I have kept hidden from  
them], you
cannot sue the buyer to get back the house."

"The tutor  describes this different
result as the "only unacceptable result", because,  to the
buyer, the common law crook [who never legally owns the property] and  the
dishonest trustee [who has legal ownership but subject to a trust] will  
look
the same."


"But this is specious and spurious. They do not  'look the same' in
any decisive sense: in terms of being detected by a buyer,  the common law 
crook
is much more detectable than the dishonest trustee: for  the dishonest 
trustee 
is the legal owner, and so that they are the person  named in the title 
deeds, 
and
that those deeds are genuine, will check  out because it is true."

"The common law
crook can only pull off a  fraudulent sale of a house by using fake deeds, 
or by
pretending to be the  person named in genuine deeds - but, in both cases, 
the
pretense is  detectable in ways that will not detect that a genuine legal 
owner
holds  subject to a trust."

"Ergo, they do not necessarily look the same  at
all."


"It is the settlos of the trust who should be  incentivised
to ensure that they choose a trustworthy trustee, something  which they can 
try
to ensure much more readily than a buyer can ensure that a  legal owner 
does not
actually hold that ownership subject to a  trust."

"Without the incentives being
allocated properly, the law  would not only become unacceptable in its 
working
but would fall into  disrepute."

Isn't that the implicature in "Oliver Twist": "The law's an  ass!"  

------------------------------------------------------------------
To change your Lit-Ideas settings (subscribe/unsub, vacation on/off,
digest on/off), visit www.andreas.com/faq-lit-ideas.html

Other related posts: