[lit-ideas] Re: Hartiana

  • From: "" <dmarc-noreply@xxxxxxxxxxxxx> (Redacted sender "Jlsperanza@xxxxxxx" for DMARC)
  • To: lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx
  • Date: Fri, 27 Mar 2015 06:20:23 -0400

My last post today!
 
P. H. Nowell-Smith was a genial member of J. L. Austin's Saturday Mornings' 
 Play Group. In his "The Logical Basis of Ethics" he is using ethics so 
genially  that he was bound to interest Hart, who was into jurisprudence, 
rather, but  which Nowell-Smith read as "legal philosophy". Nowell-Smith KNEW 
of 
Hart's  separability thesis ('morality and legality are separable, which 
does not mean  they are separated), and he invited Hart to consider the 
'logical basis'. The  trend became a fashion, and soon R. M. Hare got an 
interest 
too. With the advent  of Grice and his conversational implicature talk, the 
scenarios became more  sophisticated, and the Play Group had J. O. Urmson to 
provide the extra alleged  counter-example. That was fun!
 
Once McEvoy dismissed epistemic logic from a Popperian point of view, and I 
 would think Popper would dismiss deontic logic. It fascinated R. M. Hare, 
if not  especially H. L. A. Hart. Recall that Hare was Hart's junior, and 
that may have  something to do with it. "O" is sometimes rendered by "ought", 
but it's best to  render it by "obligation" (if you're feeling Roman). And 
deontic logic allows us  to FORMALISE what, say, Hart's conceptual analysis 
yields about  oblige-obligate.
 
The five normative statuses of the Traditional Scheme are:

it is [legally] obligatory that (OB)
it is permissible that  (PE)
it is impermissible that (IM)
it is omissible that (OM)
it is  optional that (OP)

The first three are familiar.

But the fourth is widely ignored.
 
The fifth has regularly been conflated with “it is a matter of indifference 
 that p” (by being defined in terms of one of the first three), which is 
not  really part of the traditional scheme.
 
Typically, one of the first two is taken as basic, and the others defined  
in terms of it, but any of the first four can play the same sort of 
purported  defining role. 
 
The most prevalent approach is to take the first as basic, and define the  
rest as follows:

PEp ↔ ~OB~p
IMp ↔ OB~p
OMp ↔ ~OBp
OPp ↔ (~OBp  &~OB~p).

These assert that something is legally permissible iff (if and only if)  
its negation is not legally obligatory. 
 
This is held as analytically true, but not thereby 'vacuous' and 'circular' 
 (McEvoy's qualifications in a different context, vide Hart's rule of  
recognition). something is impermissible iff its negation is obligatory,  
omissible iff it is not obligatory, and optional iff neither it nor its 
negation  
is obligatory. 
 
Call this “The Traditional Definitional Scheme (TDS)”. 
 
If one began with OB alone and considered the formulas on the right of the  
equivalences above, one could easily be led to consider them as at least  
candidate defining conditions for those on the left. 
 
Although not uncontestable, they are natural, and this scheme is still  
widely employed by anyone following Hart.
 
Now consider:
 
If OBp then p (if it is obligatory that p, then p is true).
If p  then PEp (if p is true, then it is permissible). 
 
These propositions are transparently false, for obligations can be violated 
 (as Hart well knew -- hence his need to instruct his Oxonian undergraduate 
 students on that with his "The concept of law") and impermissible  things 
do hold.  

Hart and Hartians are only interested in  deontic logics that contain 
classical propositional calculus (PC). 
 
So let's assume we add THAT as the FIRST ingredient in specifying  any 
deontic logic, so that, for example, 
 
OBp → ~~OBp
 
can be derived in any system to be considered.
 
it is obviously desirable to have 
 
OBp → ~PE~p 
 
as a THEOREM.
 
After all, this well-formed formula merely expresses one half of the  
equivalence between what would have been definiens and definiendum had we 
chosen  
the alternate scheme of definition in which “PE” was taken as basic 
instead of  “OB”. 
 
However, 
 
OBp → ~PE~p 
 
is not thus far derivable. 
 
For 
 
OBp → ~PE~p 
 
is definitionally equivalent to 
 
OBp → ~~OB~~p
 
which reduces by PC to 
 
OBp → OB~~p
 
but the latter formula is not tautological. So we cannot complete the  
proof. 

So tautology or analyticity becomes the STANDARD for the construction  of 
the system, rather than a term of abuse!
 
What we need what is perhaps the most fundamental and least controversial  
rule of inference in deontic logic, and the one characteristic of “classical 
 modal logics”:
 
OB-RE: 
 
If p ↔ q is a theorem, so is OBp ↔ OBq.
 
It is now easy to prove the equivalences corresponding to the  alternative 
definitional schemes. 
 
For example, since
 
⊢ p ↔ ~~p
 
by OB-RE, we get 
 
⊢ OBp ↔ OB~~p
 
i.e., 
 
⊢ OBp ↔ ~~OB~~p
 
which generates 
 
⊢ OBp ↔ ~PE~p
 
A deontic system, such as Hart's must contain a thesis asserting that a  
logical contradiction (conventionally denoted by “⊥”) is always omissible:
 
OD: ~OB⊥ 
 
So, for example, OD implies that it is a logical truth that it is not  
obligatory that my taxes are paid and not paid. 
 
A principle of a legal system like Hart's is that obligations cannot  
conflict:
 
NC: 
 
~(OBp & OB~p).

One paradox of deontic logic that has cross-references with Hart, Hare, and 
 Grice is Ross's Paradox (Ross 1941) -- Ross being a member of what Hart 
calls  Scandinavian realism (O. K. may reflect on this -ism). 
 
Consider:
 
(1) It is obligatory that the letter is mailed.
(2) It is obligatory  that the letter is mailed or the letter is burned. 

In "Practical Inferences", R. M. Hare (recall he was White's professor  of 
Moral Philosophy, while Hart chaired the Oxford chair of Jurisprudence)  
quotes H. P. Grice to the effect that the use of 'or' in (2) triggers the wrong 
 conversational implicature -- and so Ross's paradox dissolves once this 
type of  cancellable implication is brought to play a role. 
 
One good thing that J. L. Austin's Saturday Morning Play Group that Hart  
(being albeit Austin's senior) would occasionally attend, was J. O. Urmson. 
He  was there to provide the right counter-example. 
 
When Grice provided his analysis of 'mean', Urmson brought in the example  
of a torture (Grice turned that into bribery): the recognition of the 
intention  on the utterer, by the addressee, cannot be 'obliged', it has to be 
based on a  reason, not merely CAUSED or forced otherwise. 

It is not surprising that Urmson also provided counterexamples to  Hart's 
and Hare's legal and moral systems. 
 
One of Urmson's puzzles concerns Indifference versus Optionality:
 
Consider:
 
1) It is optional that you attend the meeting, but not a matter of  
indifference that you do so. 
 
This seems to describe something quite familiar: optional matters that are  
nonetheless not matters of indifference. 
 
But when deontic logicians and ethicists gave an operator label for the  
condition 
 
~OBp & ~OB~p
 
it was almost invariably “It is indifferent that p”, “INp”. But then it  
would seem to follow from the theorem 
 
OBp ∨ (~OBp & ~OB~p) ∨ IMp
 
that 
 
(~OBp & ~IMp) → INp
 
that is, everything that is neither obligatory nor prohibited is a matter  
of indifference. But many actions, including some heroic actions, are 
neither  obligatory nor prohibited, yet they are hardly matters of 
indifference. 
We might  put this by saying that SDL can represent optionality, but not 
indifference,  despite the fact that the latter concept has been a purported 
target for  representation since nearly its beginning.
 
Not satisfied with offering that to Hare and Hart, Urmson felt there was  
another problem: supererogation.
 
Some things are beyond the call of duty or supererogatory (e.g.,  
volunteering for a costly or risky good endeavor where others are equally  
qualified 
and no one person is obligated). Some deontic systems have  no capacity to 
represent this concept, which calls for a substantial increase in  expressive 
and logical resources. Hare and Hart were forever grateful to Urmson,  as 
was Grice. 
 
Cheers,
 
Speranza
 
Alchourron, C. Philosophical Foundations of Deontic Logic and the Logic of  
Defeasible Conditionals.” In Meyer & Wieringa.
––– Detachment and Defeasibility in Deontic Logic. Studia Logica,  57.
Alchourron, C. and Eugenio Bulygin. Normative Systems. Vienna, New York:  
Springer-Verlag.
Alchourron, C.  E. and Eugenio Bulygin, In  Hilpinen.
Alchourron, C. E. and David Makinson, In Hilpinen. 
Baker, G. P. Defeasibility and meaning. In Hart's festschrift.
Baker, G. P. Alternative mind-styles, in P. G. R. I. C. E., ed.  
Grandy/Warner. 
Grice, H. P. Aspects of reason. Clarendon Press.
Grice, H. P. Desirability, probability, and mood operators. Unpublication.  
The Grice Papers. Bancroft Library.
Hare, R. M. Practical Inferences. London: Macmillan.
Hare, R. M. Some subatomic particles of logic, Mind, repr. On the tropic,  
the clistic, the neustic, and the phrastic. 
Hart, H. L. A. The concept of law. Clarendon..
Hintikka, Jaakko. In  Grandy/Warner, P. G. R. I. C. E. -- Philosophical 
grounds of rationality:  intentions, categories, ends. Clarendon. 
Kamp, H. Free Choice Permission.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,  
74.
Nowell Smith, P. H. and E. J. Lemmon. Escapism: The Logical Basis of  
Ethics.” Mind, 69.
Ross, A. Imperatives and Logic. Theoria, 7.
Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter.  Ought Conversationally Implies Can. 
Philosophical Review. 
Urmson, J.O. Saints and Heroes. In Melden, Essays in Moral Philosophy.  
Seattle: University of Washington Press.





------------------------------------------------------------------
To change your Lit-Ideas settings (subscribe/unsub, vacation on/off,
digest on/off), visit www.andreas.com/faq-lit-ideas.html

Other related posts: