[lit-ideas] Re: Griceian Numbers

  • From: Jlsperanza@xxxxxxx
  • To: lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx
  • Date: Fri, 15 Jun 2012 21:34:15 -0400 (EDT)

Some quotes from R. Nouwen, in 
 
_http://linguistlist.org/pubs/reviews/get-review.cfm?SubID=65223_ 
(http://linguistlist.org/pubs/reviews/get-review.cfm?SubID=65223) 
 
slightly paraphrased.
 
Cheers,
 
Speranza
 
---
 
"The meaning of simple numeral expressions like 'two', 'three',  'twenty-
seven' etc. has turned out to be one of the most problematic issues  
within" Griceianism. 
 
"Part of the problem is that 
there seem to be several candidates for  'the' meaning of an English 
cardinal."
 
"Numerals can be used in many ways, three of which have 
been the focus  of discussion in the pragmatic literature of the past 
thirty to thirty five  years." 
 
'Two' as specifying exact cardinality, 'two' as 
specifying a lower  bound and 'two' as specifying an upper bound. 

"Bultinck's book on 'Grice's numerous meanings' is an attempt at  tackling 
the 
issue by comparing the most influential theoretical trend of  the past 
three decades, the so-called Griceian programme, with the results  
of an extensive corpus study of numerals. 
 
The book contains a 
detailed discussion of the legacy of the Oxford  philosopher, born near 
Birmingham, H. P. Grice and his theory of  
conversation, with particular focus on the repercussions for the  
analysis of English cardinals. 
 
It is argued that the 'conventional' 
meaning of a numeral needs to be  established by means of a corpus 
analysis. 
 
As Bultinck subsequently aims to show, such an analysis 
undermines the  neo-Gricean assumption that numerals present a 
lower bound in their coded  meaning.

Bultinck starts with an thorough discussion of Grice's original  motives 
and proposals (CHAPTER TWO). Crucial is the distinction between  
conventional meanings and implicated meanings. 
 
Whereas the former 
are to be seen as the 'coded' or 'literal' meaning  of an expression, the 
latter arise through inferences licensed by the  assumption that the 
speaker observes maxims on the quantity, quality,  relevance and 
manner of what (s)he says. Grice intended to keep the  semantics of 
expressions simple by showing that a single conventional  meaning 
could give rise to more than one meaning by means of conversational  
implicatures. 
 
The content of the conversational principles as well as 
their  formalisation have subsequently been much debated and 
Bultinck describes  these developments in considerable detail. 

While acknowledging the  general success of Grice's theory and its 
offspring, Bultinck argues that  Grice's goal to combine a theory of 
conversation with the intention of  preserving the logical meaning of 
logical expressions is misguided. 
 
He states that there is no 
methodological justification for taking the  conventional meaning of a 
logical natural language expression (like 'or',  'and', 'if...then') to be 
exactly that of their logical counterparts. 
 
Bultinck associates what is 
conventional with what is familiar and  therefore argues that frequency 
data can help determine which meaning is  more conventional than 
others. 

In CHAPTER THREE, Bultinck continues  his discussion of Grice's 
legacy, but now focusing entirely on the  literature on numerals. 
 
Most 
attention goes to the neo-Gricean line of theories that is  
labeled 'minimalism' and that is inspired by Horn's 1972 notion 
of  'scalar implicature', a generalisation over phenomena where a weak 
item on a  scale implicates the negation of the stronger items. 

Minimalists argue that if the numerous meanings displayed by 
numerals  are to be explained by means of conversational implicatures, 
then it must be  the case that their coded meanings line up in an 
entailment scale. 
 
So, numerals are thought to form an entailment scale 
such that a  sentence like ''two students came'' is entailed by the 
stronger ''three  students came''. 
 
By uttering ''two students came'', the 
speaker therefore (potentially)  implicates that the stronger alternative 
is false, thus arriving at the  meaning ''exactly two students came''. The 
entailments are accounted for by  assuming that the conventional 
meaning of a numeral like 'two' is 'at least  two'. In the following 
chapters Bultinck aims at showing that his corpus  data falsifies this 
line of thinking, but in the theoretical discussion he  also presents 
some non-empirical counterarguments, most of which are  familiar from 
the literature. 
 
His most salient critique, however, is a repetition of the  
methodological critique he presented in chapter two. Bultinck argues  
that what Grice aimed at with his notion of conventional meaning was 
a  standard meaning. Bultinck proposes to identify conventional 
meaning with  ''familiar meaning''. Conventionality is thus equated with 
a relative high  level of frequency. He argues that this implies that 
conventional meanings  are frequent. The minimalist's choice for a 
conventional 'at least' meaning,  however, is not based on frequency at 
all. In fact, conventional meanings  are solely chosen on the basis of 
their potential for conversational  inferences.

In chapter three, there is furthermore a short discussion of  the 
underspecification account (Carston 1988), where the ''logical form'' of  
a numeral is underdetermined and can be enriched by specifying 
with 'at  least', 'at most', 'exactly' or even 'approximately'. Some other 
positions  (called 'marginal' by Bultinck), like those arguing for 
bilateral  
conventional meanings or ambiguity, are discussed as well.

In CHAPTER  FOUR, a ''general corpus analysis'' is discussed which 
aims at discovering  the different forms and functions of numerals. The 
analysis involves one  thousand occurrences of ''two'' from the British 
National Corpus. In chapter  five, Bultinck analyses the core meaning 
of numerals, namely the cardinal  one. Chapter four, however, is 
focused on a more general analysis which  aside from taking the 
syntactic form and function into account, focuses on  all possible ways 
of using a numeral. 
 
Apart from the core use of the specification of 
cardinality, these  include the numeral as a label, the numeral as a 
temporal indicator and the  numeral as a mathematical primitive. 
Bultinck isolates a wealth of variation  in usages and discusses the 
underlying corpus data in great detail. He  stresses that the data 
clearly demonstrate that it is a mistake to simply  assume that the 
meaning of numerals can be reduced to a notion of  cardinality. One 
clear result of the analysis, however, is a correspondence  between 
adnominal uses and the expression of cardinality. 
 
Almost all 
adnominal numerals in some sense express the cardinality of  a group. 
Bultinck tries to come to a hierarchy of numeral constructions in  terms 
of the degree of cardinality that is involved and concludes that ''the  
expression of cardinality is clearly the most important function of 'two''' 
 
(p. 153), followed by the expression of measurement, which, as  
acknowledged by Bultinck, in many respects involves cardinality as  
well.

In CHAPTER FIVE, a corpus analysis is presented that focuses on  
what kind of meanings cardinal uses of numerals display. It is this  
analysis that is supposed to contribute to the issue of the conventional  
meaning of 'two'. Again, Bultinck refers to the corpus method as ''the  
methodological outcome of [Grice's] theoretical insights'' (p.  168).

Bultinck distinguishes four possible meanings (pp. 176,177):  

''at least n': necessarily n + possibly more than n;

'at most n': possibly n + not possible more than n;

'exactly n': necessarily n + not possible more than n + not possible  
less than n''; and

'absolute value n': non-modal, the group of elements denoted by the 
NP  is determined as having n elements.

Crucial here is the assumption that  the first three of these meanings 
involve modal statements about  cardinality. The 'absolute value n' 
meaning, on the other hand, is  relatively simple. In fact, Bultinck 
maintains that it is 'cognitively'  simple, since it refers to nothing more 
than cardinality of a group, and  that the other interpretations are 
therefore in some sense marked. That is,  the first three meanings 
make what is said (understood in a non-Gricean way)  about the 
cardinality much more prominent than the 'absolute value'  
interpretation does. 

The majority of occurrences of 'two' turn out  to be either of 
the 'absolute value'-type or of the 'exactly n'-type. 
 
Bultinck notices that 
the 'exactly n' readings are mostly caused by  definite markers. There 
are no findings in the corpus of 'absolute value'  uses with such 
markers. 
 
This observation also serves to explain the distribution of the  
different usages over different syntactic positions. For instance, the  
majority of direct objects contain numerals of the 'absolute value' type,  
whereas the majority of numerals in adverbial phrases are used 
as  'exactly n'. According to Bultinck this distribution is simply a reflex 
of  
the attested fact that direct objects are generally good candidates for  
introducing new topics, whereas it is less likely that material in  
adverbial phrases is there to (existentially) introduce a new  referent.

In subject position, occurrences of 'two' without definite  markers are 
mostly 'absolute value' or 'exactly n'. But the difference  between these 
two usages is blurred. 
 
The trend is that subject position indefinite 
numerals are less likely  to allow for a subsequent revision of the 
involved cardinality than object  indefinite numerals. Bultinck proposes 
that this is due to the fact that it  is marked to use a subject for the 
introducing of a new referent. The  focused use of the numeral hints at 
excluding the possibility of there being  more than the 'n' elements that 
are expressed. This means that there is a  continuum from 'absolute 
value' to 'exactly n' meanings. In 'pure absolute  value' use there is a 
neutrality toward the possibility of there being more  elements. This 
neutrality is reduced in subject position. A further finding  supports this 
idea of a continuum. In predicative constructions (such as  existential 
there sentences), most samples show the absolute value meaning  of 
the numeral. 
 
Bultinck's idea is that such constructions hardly change 
the default  'absolute value' interpretation of the numeral. Although 
Bultinck is careful  not to present it as a clear result from his corpus 
research, he  hypothesises that the continuum from 'absolute value' 
to 'exactly n' is  paired with a scale of syntactic constructions, ranging 
from existential  there sentences, to objects, to subjects, to adverbials. 

The picture  emerging from this is one where a great multitude of 
factors influence the  'value interpretation' of a numeral. In particular, 
it 
seems generally the  case that when there is an 'exactly n' 
interpretation of the ''meaning  complex'' that contains the numeral, this 
meaning can be reduced to a  combination of the 'absolute value' 
meaning and the influence of other  co-textual factors. 
 
It follows 
that ''[the] 'absolute value' interpretation is the  starting-point for the 
interpretation of 'two''' (p. 225), or as Bultinck  concludes in chapter 
six, ''the conventional meaning (the ''coded content'')  of 'two' is 
the 'absolute value' meaning'' (p. 307).

The corpus  analysis shows that 'at least n' uses of numerals are 
highly infrequent  (3,9%). This, Bultinck claims, is highly problematic for 
the neo-Griceans.  In fact, the corpus analysis shows that the few 'at 
least' uses that are  found are all due to the co-occurrence with a 
linguistic element and, in  most cases, that element is 'at least'.

Another finding from the corpus  discredits the neo-Gricean account of 
numerals in another way. 
 
One of the traditional arguments for 
assuming the 'at least n' meaning  to be conventional is that 
were 'exactly n' conventional, then it would be  redundant to combine 
the numeral with 'exactly'. It is not and hence, the  argument 
goes, 'exactly n' cannot be the coded meaning of 'n'. The corpus  
shows, however, some very clear facts about numeral modifiers 
(called  'restrictions' by Bultinck). The most common kind of 
modification is with  'at least' (44.8%), whereas combinations of 'two' 
with 'exactly' are  relatively rare at 9.5%. If the neo-Gricean argument 
holds, exactly the  reverse distribution of 'exactly' and 'at least' would 
be  expected.

The first half of the book is devoted to the discussion of the  literature 
on (neo-)Gricean implicatures in general and the pragmatics of  
numerals in particular. A shorter discussion might have been more  
effective, since one has to wait a long time for Bultinck's main feat, the  
discussion of his corpus study of numerals (chapters four and five).  

Furthermore, the literature discussion is often overly detailed and  
repetitive. For instance, some of the arguments Bultinck discusses in  
the chapter on Gricean pragmatics are repeated in both his discussion 
of  the literature on numerals and in the discussion of the corpus data.  
Nevertheless, it is certainly admirable that Bultinck so successfully  
weaves together discussions from linguistic pragmatics, corpus  
linguistics and cognitive linguistics. Although tedious at some points,  
the many repetitions might actually guarantee that this book is suitable  
for the broad audience it sets out to reach.

A more serious problem  is the fact that the discussion in chapters two 
and three is in many ways  dated. Browsing the references, one finds 
that the most recent literature  that is being discussed dates from 2001 
(the book is published in 2005). Of  course, many of the high points of 
the discussion of scalar implicatures can  be traced back to the 1970s 
and 1980s, so it is perhaps not entirely  unexpected to find mostly 
older literature. However, in the past few years  the study of 
implicatures and numerals has flourished once again. Now, there  is a 
wealth of new findings and theoretic proposals (e.g. Geurts 1998,  
Chierchia 2002, Recanati 2003, van Rooy and Schulz 2004). 
Furthermore,  an increase in the interest of psycholinguists into 
pragmatic issues has  lead to a considerable amount of empirical data 
challenging the traditional  theoretic approaches to make more precise 
predictions (see, for instance,  Noveck 2001, Papafragou and 
Musolino 2003 and, especially, Musolino 2004).  Unfortunately, such 
recent works are completely absent from Bultinck's  discussions and 
arguments. This may be explained by the fact that this book,  as I 
understand it, is a published version of Bultinck's dissertation which  
dates from 2001. Curiously, however, this fact is not mentioned in the  
book.

The main objective of Bultinck's corpus analysis seems to be to  
discredit the idea that numerals carry a conventional meaning that  
involves a lower bound. With this in mind, I think the three most  
relevant findings are: (A) the corpus is argued to display the  
infrequency of this alleged coded meaning; (B) the data suggest that  
there are 'numerous meanings' associated with English cardinals and 
that  these are less rigidly distributed than the neo-Gricean programme 
would have  it; and (C) the 'absolute value' meaning is the most basic 
one of these  numerous meanings.

It is not entirely clear to what extend Bultinck's 'at  least n' meaning 
corresponds to the lower bound conventional meaning  defended by 
the minimalists. I doubt whether the neo-Griceans really had a  modal 
coded meaning in mind. It is certainly not the case that the lower  
bound meaning necessarily involves modality. It is quite easy to 
imagine  a 'cognitively simple' lower bound analysis which simply 
describes the  cardinality of a group as being 'greater or equal than n'. 
In fact, such a  proposal comes very close to Bultinck's own 'absolute 
value' meaning. This  becomes clear from Bultinck's specification of the 
four candidate meanings.  The 'at least n' meaning is described 
as ''necessarily n + possibly more  then n'' (p. 176). Note that in this 
definition, one needs to assume that  the number symbol 'n' has a 
greater-or-equal reading itself. If the  cardinality of a group is 
necessarily 'n', how can it at the same time be  possible that this 
cardinality is 'more than n'? A formulation like this one  presupposes 
once again that numerals somehow line up in entailment scales.  It 
follows that the 'absolute value' meaning is really a lower bound  
meaning. Consequently, one could characterise Bultinck's proposal as  
minimalistic, except that the conversational implicatures have been  
replaced by co-textual factors that trigger modal cardinality  statements.

So how well does this proposal account for the data? 
 
The 'absolute 
value' meaning of numerals seems consistent with the data  in the 
corpus. It is important, however, to explain in detail how the  
compositional meaning of numerals is defined, especially since these  
very meanings have turned out to be so remarkably deceptive.  
Unfortunately, the semantic processes Bultinck refers to are often not  
specified enough to assess how the sentential meanings are derived 
from  a single core lexical meaning. 

Nevertheless, 'numerous meanings'  contains a wealth of data and 
ideas that will stimulate the ongoing  discussion of the semantics of 
simplex and complex English numerals. Anyone  working on a linguistic 
topic that is somehow related to numeral meaning  will definitely find a 
lot to learn in this book, especially since  Bultinck's most important 
point, I feel, is not theoretical but  methodological. The data are much 
more varied and complex than the  neo-Gricean theories have 
assumed. On the basis of this, Bultinck argues  convincingly that it is a 
mistake to search for 'the' meaning of English  cardinals. 

REFERENCES

Carston, R. 1988. Implicature, explicature  and truth-theoretic 
semantics. In Kempson, R. (ed.), Mental Representations:  The 
interface between Language and Reality. 

Chierchia, G. 2004.  Scalar Implicatures, Polarity Phenomena, and the 
Syntax/Pragmatics  Interface. In Belletti, B. (ed.), Structures and 
Beyond: The Cartography of  Syntactic Structures. Vol. 3. New York, 
NY: Oxford University  Press.

Geurts, B. 1998. Scalars. In Ludewig, P. and Geurts, B. (eds.)  
Lexicalische Semantik aus Cognitiver Sicht. Tuebingen: Gunter Narr.  
95-117.

Horn, L. 1972. On the Semantic Properties of Logical  Operators in 
English. UCLA dissertation. Distributed by Indiana University  
Linguistics Club, 1976. 

Musolino, J. 2004. The semantics and  acquisition of number words: 
Integrating linguistic and developmental  perspectives. Cognition 93(1): 
1-41.

Noveck, I. 2001. When children  are more logical than adults: 
Experimental investigations of scalar  implicature. Cognition 79: 165-
188. 

Papafragou, A. and Musolino, J.  2003. Scalar implicatures: 
Experiments at the semantics-pragmatics  interface. Cognition 86(3): 
253-282.

Recanati, F. 2003. Embedded  Implicatures, Philosophical Perspectives 
17(1): 299-332.

van Rooy, R.  and Schulz, K. 2004. Exhaustive interpretation of 
complex sentences. Journal  of Logic, Language and Information, 13:  
491-519.


------------------------------------------------------------------
To change your Lit-Ideas settings (subscribe/unsub, vacation on/off,
digest on/off), visit www.andreas.com/faq-lit-ideas.html

Other related posts: