[lit-ideas] Re: Grice and Lowe and the four categories

  • From: Donal McEvoy <donalmcevoyuk@xxxxxxxxxxx>
  • To: "lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx" <lit-ideas@xxxxxxxxxxxxx>
  • Date: Wed, 8 Jan 2014 11:01:34 +0000 (GMT)


Walter writes: “That I engaged in s-o-h is an allegation
made by Donal, not you.  Sorry for not being clear.”
 
But is it correct that Donal made “an allegation” that
Walter “engaged in s-o-h”? If not, Walter should perhaps be sorry for this 
suggestion
(or indeed “allegation”) - made after I already posted how my use of ‘s-o-h’ is
not ad hominem but rather addresses the deceptive character of a fallacious 
comparison/argument.
 
Donal had commented "There is a kind of
sleight-of-hand in the comparison between being courageous and knowing how to
tie one's laces." 
 
This comment does not mention Walter, and it does not
mention anything Walter or anybody is “engaged in”. It falls miles away from
alleging that Walter has deliberately or intentionally “engaged in” s-o-h.
Yet some might say that the implicature of Walter’s “engaged in s-o-h” is that
the person deliberately or intentionally “engaged in s-o-h”. Given
such an implicature, then Walter uses language that implies (whether
deliberately or intentionally on Walter’s part I know not) that Donal makes the
allegation that Walter has deliberately or intentionally set out to deceive. But
this does not follow, neither inevitably nor by probability, from the comment
that "There is a kind of sleight-of-hand in the comparison between being
courageous and knowing how to tie one's laces."
 
Walter has treated that comment as an ad hominem, even as a
mere ad hominem, when there is a perfectly obvious way of treating it as not ad
hominem at all – especially as the comment itself is expressed entirely in
non-ad hominem rather ad hominem terms i.e. it refers to a “kind of” s-o-h in a 
“comparison” and not to any human and what
they are alleged to be “engaged in”. 
 
This comment about a “kind of” s-o-h “in the comparison” was
preface to my making a number of points about the limitations of the comparison
as some kind of argument. Again none of those points and limitations dragged in
“Walter” or dragged in what Walter was “engaged in”. Again those points and
limitations concerned the argument and were not concerned with ad hominem. For
example, Walter made the point that knowledge is not adequate to give a person
courage, and I made the point that knowledge is not adequate to give one the
ability to tie laces either – so Walter’s “comparison” or contrast between 
‘having
courage’ and tying laces (or “shoes” if Walter prefers) does not ground any
valid argument to distinguish the two cases in this regard. There is nothing ad
hominem about this point. 
 
That point is one of many points made in my post that Walter
does nothing to engage because he has ‘ad hominised’ the post: taking what were
points against his argument as some kind of personal attack on his integrity. 
 
Two or more can play at this ‘ad hominising’ game, which is
a very easy game to play, as may be shown as follows. We could treat Walter’s
post not as a genuinely felt complaint based on a misplaced sense of personal
affront but as a mere ad hominem against Donal: the mere ad hominem being that
Donal is the kind of person who posts purely personal attacks of a merely ad
hominem type and actually raises no points that concern the arguments on the
table. This mere ad hominem interpretation by Walter thus enables Walter to
evade the substantive points made in Donal’s post, for example that knowledge
is not adequate to give one the ability to tie laces anymore than it is
adequate to give one courage. In particular, this ‘ad hominising’ interpretation
by Walter means Walter need not engage what is perhaps the most important point
in Donal’s post – that a ‘folk psychology’ approach to knowledge is inadequate
and flawed.
 
Do I think Walter is deliberately and intentionally “engaged
in” mere ad hominem of this sort against Donal? No, I think Walter is genuinely
and personally affronted – and that this may have been, in part, sparked by the
use of the expression “sleight-of-hand”. 
 
But is Walter is justified in this sense of personal
affront? No more justified than it is justified to move from the comment
"There is a kind of sleight-of-hand in the comparison between being
courageous and knowing how to tie one's laces" to the conclusion that the
person putting forward the comparison is deliberately or intentionally setting
out to deceive. And this is no more justified than moving from “There is a kind
of sleight-of-hand in Descartes’ cogito”
to the conclusion that Descartes put forward his cogito in a deliberate attempt 
to deceive. No more justified than
moving from Wittgenstein’s comment about “the decisive step in the
conjuring-trick has been made” to the conclusion that Wittgenstein thinks
philosophers deliberately set out to deceive. No more justified than moving
from “There is sleight-of-hand in the use of “is” here as it varies between the
“is” of identity and the “is” of predication” to the conclusion that the
variable sense of “is” is part of some deliberate attempt to deceive.
 
If Walter is not justified in moving from "There is a
kind of sleight-of-hand in the comparison between being courageous and knowing
how to tie one's laces" to “That I engaged in s-o-h is an allegation made
by Donal”, then perhaps Walter should retract that last statement – or at least
not repeat it as if it is a straightforward statement of fact. 
 
My previous post, addressing Walter’s ad hominising
interpretation of the s-o-h comment, advised: “People should beware treating a
non-ad hominem argument as an ad hominem argument: it is easy to do so, but it
means discussion in non-ad hominem terms is impeded.” There is not only the
danger of impeding discussion:- beyond a point such ad hominising interpretation
itself risks being regarded as deliberate and intentional misrepresentation of
an ad hominising sort.
 
Donal



On Wednesday, 8 January 2014, 11:00, Donal McEvoy <donalmcevoyuk@xxxxxxxxxxx> 
wrote:
 
This is a test post entirely.

D





On Tuesday, 7 January 2014, 23:19, "Jlsperanza@xxxxxxx" <Jlsperanza@xxxxxxx> 
wrote:
 
In a message dated 1/7/2014 4:01:40 P.M. Eastern  Standard Time, 
omarkusto@xxxxxxxxx writes:
Hm... so there are nouns that  denote things and adjectives
 that denote 
properties of things... and nouns can  be concrete or abstract... I seem to 
remember being taught something very  similar to this in the lower grades of 
the elementary, only my elementary  teacher did not present it as a 
metaphysical theory. :)

Well, yes.

I suppose the idea was the same when Dionisio (was that his name?) thought  
of writing the first 'grammar' (folk grammar, as Donal McEvoy would 
qualify?)  and revised Aristotle. Grammar is a branch of philosophy!

The mediaevals (as Geary calls them, as implicating they KNEW it) called  
theirselves 'modistae': abstractum/concetrum, etc. are indeed metaphysical 
(or  ontological as I prefer) distinctions which are verbal in origin. 

Aristotle was a good one in MULTIPLYING 'partes orationis'. Think that  
during Plato's time, there was only noun and verb!

Below is an expansion on
 Lowe, with thanks to Robin Hendry and Matthew  
Ratcliffe.

E. Jonathan Lowe was born in Dover, England, on 24th March 1950, and died  
on January 5th 2014.
E. Paul Grice was born in Harborne, Warwickshire in 1913 and died in  1988.

Lowe went to Cambridge to read Natural Sciences in 1968.
Grice didn't.

However, Lowe changed to History after one year and was awarded a BA  
(first class) in 1971. This was a good thing, in the words of Sellars and  
Yeatman.

After that, Lowe switched, again, to Philosophy and moved, rightly, to  
Oxford, where he was awarded his BPhil and DPhil degrees in 1974 and 1975,  
supervised by the Australian-born philosopher Romano Harré and Simon W.  
Blackburn -- formerly of Pembroke -- respectively. 

Blackburn was at the time obsessed with Grice (or wasn't). His "Spreading  
the word: groundings in the philosophy of
 language" has an excellent full  
chapter on Grice. Blackburn is aware of the first and secondary Griceian  
bibliography, and has a good sense of humour to boot.

After a brief period teaching at Reading, Lowe joins the Department of  
Philosophy at Durham (in Durhamshire, as Speranza likes to say) in 1980, where  
he stayed for the rest of his career. This was an excellent choice, since  
Durhamshire is one of the most picturesque, and most English, of England's  
shires.

Lowe was promoted to Senior Lecturer in 1990 and to Reader in 1992. 

Finally, he was promoted to Full Professor in 1995.

Grice's career was similar. After his BA and MA (he never earned a DPhil),  
Oxon., he taught for a year ("or two" as he liked to say, merely  
implicaturishly) at Rossall, in the North of Watford, he went back to Oxford 
for  
what people thought would be "the rest
 of his career".

Unexpectedly, though, he was offered the William James Lectureships in  
Harvard in 1967, when he took the occasion to find the right house to buy (of  
all places) up the Berkeley hills, in Berkeley. He was promoted instantly to 
Full Professor of Philosophy in 1968, and taught ONLY graduate courses. 

During Lowe's time at Durham, Lowe established himself as one of  the world’
s leading philosophers, publishing twelve single-authored books, four  
co-edited collections and well over 200 articles in journals and edited 
volumes. 

On the other hand, Grice published preciously little. He was fond of his  
'unpublications', though, which, "by far exceed the number of my 
publications". 

Grice died in 1988. His first book came out in 1989. One in 1991 and  
another in 2001 'soon' followed. ("What _is_ the implicature of 'soon'?")

We may need a
 checklist of Lowe's output.

And a cross-reference:

Lowe and Grice.
Keywords: H. P. Grice, E. J. Lowe.

Lowe's scholarship was strikingly broad, ranging from Early Modern  
Philosophy through to the interpretation of quantum mechanics.

Grice especialised in Kantotle and dismissed Russell's mot on stone-age  
metaphysics -- "stone-age physics, and proud of it!" he would claim.

Lowe's most important and sustained contributions were to philosophy of  
mind, philosophical logic and especially metaphysics.

Grice's most important contribution was his self, too!

(Although dictionary entries 'explicate': philosophy of language).

Lowe adopts what he called a "realist" conception of metaphysics as an  
autonomous discipline concerned with the fundamental structure of reality, as  
exemplified by his important book "The Possibility of Metaphysics" (Oxford  
University Press, 1998). 

On the other hand, Grice's main early contribution to metaphysics was via  
the tutorials and joint seminars with his student P. F. Strawson. Grice 
would  note a few reflection owed to himself in Strawson's "Individuals: an 
essay in  descriptive metaphysics". Lowe's "Possibility of Metaphysics" may be 
a 
rejoinder  to Strawson's neo-Kantian negation of it in "The bounds of 
sense" -- an essay on  Kant's very rejection of the "Possibility of 
Metaphysics", 
as Lowe entitles his  essay.

Popper possibly also was irrirated when people identified him as 'rejecting 
the possibility of metaphysics' (alla Vienna Circle). So Lowe's essay is  
_topical_!

Metaphysics, Lowe maintains, should take common sense as its starting  
point -- what Grice calls 'folksy' -- but cfr. Donal McEvoy's for arguments 
that 
what folks say is never "'nuff" (I
 use my own dialect there: _love_ 
"'nuff")  while at the same time acknowledging that aspects of common sense 
will 
need to  be revised or abandoned. 

This second bit is controversial: when do (the folks) find out that the  
folks are wrong? (especially in abstract areas like metaphysics?)

Metaphysics, Lowe adds, should also retain a healthy respect for  science 
but at the same time resist what after Grice we may call the Devil of  
Scientism.

The role of metaphysics, after all, is to illuminate features of reality  
that empirical scientific enquiry inevitably presupposes (in Collingwood's 
use  of the term, discussed by Grice/Strawson/Pears in their seminal 
"Metaphysics" in  Pears, "The nature of metaphysics" -- originally BBC Third 
programme lectures,  1957 -- cf. Helm, this forum, for an expansion on the 
concept.

Metaphysics (in both its
 variants, Ontology and Eschatology [the theory  of 
category barriers and transcategorial epithets], then -- to use Griceian  
parlance) is therefore the most fundamental form of enquiry and - as Lowe 
also  emphasises – something that is extremely difficult to do -- as opposed to 
'gardening', or merely 'linguistic botany' of this or that sort. 

But, Lowe insists, there are no cheap short-cuts, and no piece-meal  
solutions to metaphysical problems. 

Metaphysics is to be done systematically and patiently, as Aristotle  did.

Lowe’s approach drew inspiration, if not from Kantotle (as Grice's  did), 
from Aristotle and the brilliant English philosopher Locke, amongst  others, 
both of whom retained a foothold in common sense. 

Locke was obsessed with the corpuscular theory of vision, and his  
metaphysics is empiricist. Romano Harré possibly was influential
 here. Madden  and 
Harré, after all, think that Locke and Hume, into the bargain, are WRONG and  
that empiricist metaphysics is a no-no (vide "Causal Powers"). Lowe was  
interested in Locke's discussion of a 'kind' and a natural kind in particular, 
also Locke's philosophy of colour. 

Lowe's metaphysical writings addressed a range of themes,  including:

-- volition (and since we were discussing with Donal, Omar, and Walter  'to 
know' as 'to believe' (truly and in a justified way, we may want to 
approach  'want' -- or not.

-- personhood -- cfr. Grice, "Personal identity", Mind, 1941. Cfr.  Parfit.

-- agency -- cfr. Grice, "Actions and Events", Pacific Philosophical  
Quarterly, 1986.

-- mental causation. A topic that Donal McEvoy has approached in this forum 
vis–à–vis Popper's 'interactionism'. 

-- identity -- cfr. the Grice-Myro of
 relative identity. Also Geach.

-- truth (as in Ramsey's redundancy theory of truth: "To say that I believe 
it is raining, and to say that I believe it is true that is raining are 
the same  thing").

-- essentialism and 

-- most notably, ontological categories. 

In recent years, one of Lowe's many notable achievements was the  
formulation of a new ‘four-category ontology’, which he proposed as a  
metaphysical 
foundation for all empirical scientific thought. 

These four categories should NOT be confused with Grice's four categories  
(conversational categories, echoing Kant: quantitas-qualitas-relatio-modus), 
although there ARE connections: Kant hoped to reduce Aristotle's ten 
categories  to four, and Lowe ends up with the same mathematical result.

One of Lowe's brilliant examples involved the distinction between

'red' and 'apple'

in 'red
 apple'.

This distinction allows for the categories being _four_.  It is based  on 
the grammar of English, rather than, perhaps, Greek! -- but as Omar K. points 
out, it is in the very structure of the teaching of grammar even if 
grammarians  are sometimes not clear as to the metaphysical bases for their 
claims. (Was  Dionisio?)

The most detailed account of this appears in Lowe's essay, "The  
Four-Category Ontology" (properly published with Oxford University Press, 
2006). 

Throughout his life, Lowe was guided by a kind of faith in our ability  to 
discover the fundamental structure of reality through metaphysical thought.  
This was a good thing.

Lowe was spurred on by a constant sense of puzzlement, fascination and  
bewilderment at the existence and nature of reality, and would not let  
extraneous considerations distract him from a resolute search
 for truth. 

And so was Grice.

Cheers,

Speranza

Lowe writes: "We should gravitate  towards the fourth system of   ontology 
identified earlier, the system which  acknowledges three  distinct 
ontological categories as being fundamental and   indispensable — the  category 
of 
objects, or individual substances; the  category  of universals;  and the 
category of tropes, or, as I shall  henceforth prefer to  call them,  modes. It 
is then but a short   step to my own variant of this system,  which 
distinguishes between two  fundamental categories of universal, one  whose  
instances are objects  and the other whose instances are  modes. ... This 
distinction   is  mirrored in language by the distinction between sortal and  
adjectival  general  terms — that is, between such
 general terms as  'planet'  and 
'flower' 
on the one hand and such general terms as 'red'  and 'round' on the  other. 
... The former denote kinds of object, while the  latter denote  properties 
of  objects. ... The four-category  ontology ...provides, I  
believe, a uniquely satisfactory metaphysical  foundation for natural 
science."


------------------------------------------------------------------
To change your Lit-Ideas settings (subscribe/unsub, vacation on/off,
digest on/off), visit www.andreas.com/faq-lit-ideas.html

Other related posts: